2001-filho-1 ref03.pdf

47
753 Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001 DEBATE DEBATE For a General Theory of Health: preliminary epistemological and anthropological notes Para uma Teoria Geral da Saúde: anotações epistemológicas e antropológicas preliminares 1 Instituto de Saúde Coletiva , Un i versidade Fe d e ral da Ba h i a . Rua Pa d re Feijó 29, 4 o a n d a r, S a l va d o r, BA 4 0 1 1 0 - 1 7 0 , Bra s i l . Naomar de Almeida Filho 1 Abstract In order to conduct a preliminary evaluation of the conditions allowing for a General Theory of Health, the author explores two important structural dimensions of the scientific health field: the socio-anthropological dimension and the epistemological dimension. As a preliminary semantic framework, he adopts the following definitions in English and Portuguese for two series of meanings: disease = patologia, disorder = transtorno, illness = enfermidade, sickness = doença, and malady = moléstia. He begins by discussing some sociological theories and biomedical con- cepts of health-disease, w h i c h , despite their limitations, can be used as a point of depart u re for this undert a k i n g ,g i ven the dialectical and multidimensional nature of the disease-illness-sick- ness complex (DIS). Se c o n d , he presents and evaluates some underlying socio-anthro p o l o g i c a l theories of disease, taking advantage of the opportunity to highlight the semeiologic treatment of health-disease through the theory of “s i g n s , m e a n i n g s , and health pra c t i c e s”. T h i rd , he analyze s s e ve ral epistemological issues relating to the Health theme, seeking to justify its status as a scien- tific object. Finally, the author focuses the discussion on a proposal to systematize various health concepts as an initial stage for the theoretical construction of the Collective Health field. Key words Epidemiologic Mo d e l s ;T h e o retical Models; Epidemiologic Methods Resumo Com o objetivo de avaliar preliminarmente as condições de possibilidade de uma Teo- ria Ge ral da Saúde, ex p l o ra-se duas das mais importantes dimensões estruturantes do campo científico da saúde: a dimensão sócio-antropológica e a dimensão epistemológica. Como mar- cação semântica pre l i m i n a r, p ropõe-se uma fixação de sentido em Po rtuguês para duas séries s i g n i f i c a n t e s : d i s e a s e = patologia, d i s o rd e r = tra n s t o r n o, i l l n e s s = enfermidade, s i c k n e s s = d o e n ç a , m a l a d y = moléstia. In i c i a l m e n t e , discute-se algumas teorias sociológicas e concepções biomédicas de saúde-doença que, não obstante suas limitações, sem dúvida poderão ser tomadas como ponto de partida para este esforço, dado o caráter dialético e multidimensional do Com- p l exo D-E-P (doença-enfermidade-patologia). Em segundo lugar, algumas abordagens sócio- antropológicas articuladoras de teorias de doença são apresentadas e avaliadas, aproveitando- se a oportunidade para destacar um tratamento semiológico da saúde-doença, através da teoria dos “s i g n o s , significados e práticas de saúde”. Em terc e i ro lugar, analisam-se algumas questões epistemológicas em torno do tema Saúde, buscando justificar o seu estatuto de objeto científico. Fi n a l m e n t e , coloca-se em discussão uma proposta de sistematização de distintos conceitos de saúde, como etapa inicial para a construção teórica do campo da Saúde Coletiva. Palavras-chave Modelos Epidemiológicos; Modelos Teóricos; Métodos Epidemiológicos

Upload: luisabernalr

Post on 24-Dec-2015

34 views

Category:

Documents


4 download

TRANSCRIPT

Page 1: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

7 5 3

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

D E B ATE D E B AT E

For a General Theory of Health: pre l i m i n a ryepistemological and anthropological notes

Para uma Teoria Geral da Saúde: anotaçõesepistemológicas e antropológicas pre l i m i n a re s

1 Instituto de Saúde Coletiva ,Un i versidade Fe d e ral daBa h i a . Rua Pa d re Feijó 29,4o a n d a r, S a l va d o r, BA 4 0 1 1 0 - 1 7 0 , Bra s i l .

Naomar de Almeida Filho 1

A b s t r a c t In order to conduct a pre l i m i n a ry evaluation of the conditions allowing for a Ge n e ra lT h e o ry of He a l t h , the author ex p l o res two important structural dimensions of the scientific healthf i e l d : the socio-anthropological dimension and the epistemological dimension. As a pre l i m i n a rysemantic fra m ew o rk , he adopts the following definitions in English and Po rtuguese for two seriesof meanings: disease = p a t o l o g i a, d i s o rder = t ra n s t o rn o, illness = e n f e rm i d a d e, sickness = d o e n ç a,and malady = m o l é s t i a. He begins by discussing some sociological theories and biomedical con-cepts of health-disease, w h i c h , despite their limitations, can be used as a point of depart u re forthis undert a k i n g ,g i ven the dialectical and multidimensional nature of the disease-illness-sick-ness complex (DIS). Se c o n d , he presents and evaluates some underlying socio-anthro p o l o g i c a ltheories of disease, taking advantage of the opportunity to highlight the semeiologic treatment ofhealth-disease through the theory of “s i g n s , m e a n i n g s , and health pra c t i c e s”. T h i rd , he analyze ss e ve ral epistemological issues relating to the Health theme, seeking to justify its status as a scien-tific object. Fi n a l l y, the author focuses the discussion on a proposal to systematize various healthconcepts as an initial stage for the theoretical construction of the Collective Health field.Key word s Epidemiologic Mo d e l s ;T h e o retical Mo d e l s ; Epidemiologic Me t h o d s

R e s u m o Com o objetivo de avaliar preliminarmente as condições de possibilidade de uma Te o-ria Ge ral da Saúde, ex p l o ra-se duas das mais importantes dimensões estruturantes do campocientífico da saúde: a dimensão sócio-antropológica e a dimensão epistemológica. Como mar-cação semântica pre l i m i n a r, p ropõe-se uma fixação de sentido em Po rtuguês para duas sériess i g n i f i c a n t e s : d i s e a s e = patologia, d i s o rd e r = tra n s t o r n o, i l l n e s s = enfermidade, s i c k n e s s =d o e n ç a , m a l a d y = moléstia. In i c i a l m e n t e , discute-se algumas teorias sociológicas e concepçõesbiomédicas de saúde-doença que, não obstante suas limitações, sem dúvida poderão ser tomadascomo ponto de partida para este esforço, dado o caráter dialético e multidimensional do Com-p l exo D-E-P (doença-enfermidade-patologia). Em segundo lugar, algumas abordagens sócio-a n t ropológicas art i c u l a d o ras de teorias de doença são apresentadas e ava l i a d a s , a p rove i t a n d o -se a oportunidade para destacar um tratamento semiológico da saúde-doença, a t ravés da teoriados “s i g n o s , significados e práticas de saúde”. Em terc e i ro lugar, analisam-se algumas questõesepistemológicas em torno do tema Saúde, buscando justificar o seu estatuto de objeto científico.Fi n a l m e n t e , coloca-se em discussão uma proposta de sistematização de distintos conceitos des a ú d e , como etapa inicial para a construção teórica do campo da Saúde Coletiva .P a l a v r a s - c h a v e Modelos Ep i d e m i o l ó g i c o s ; Modelos Te ó r i c o s ; Métodos Ep i d e m i o l ó g i c o s

Page 2: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

I n t ro d u c t i o n

In the va rious disciplines comprising the so-called health field, we observe timid attemptsat conceptually constructing the “ h e a l t h” ob-ject (Cze resnia, 1999: Levine, 1995), in contra s twith the extensive efforts at developing bio-medical disease models (Abed, 1993; Be r l i n g u e r,1988; Mu r p h y, 1965; Pérez - Ta m a yo, 1988;Temkin, 1963), emphasizing the individual andsub-individual levels of analysis.

In order to conduct a pre l i m i n a ry assess-ment of the conditions allowing for a Ge n e ra lT h e o ry of Health, I propose herewith to exploretwo important underlying dimensions in thescientific field of health: the socio-anthro p o-logical dimension and the epistemological di-mension. The epidemiological dimension ofthe health concept was the object of a specificpaper (Almeida Fi l h o, in press). Despite re c o g-nizing its importance and founding ro l e, thebiological dimension will not be cove red here,e xcept insofar as it proves indispensable toc l a rify some specific issue in the health-diseasemodels analyzed herein. Aspects pertaining tothe etymology of the term “ h e a l t h” we re theobject of a related article (Almeida Fi l h o, 2000).

First, I intend to discuss some sociologicalt h e o ries of disease-illness-sickness and bio-medical concepts of health, which, despite thelimitations discussed below, can doubtless betaken as the point of depart u re for this under-taking, given the dialectical and multidimen-sional nature of the health-disease dyad. Se c-ond, I will present and assess seve ral underly-ing socio-anthropological approaches to theo-ries of disease, taking advantage of the oppor-tunity to highlight the semeiologic tre a t m e n tof health-disease through the theory of “s i g n s,m e a n i n g s, and health pra c t i c e s”. T h i rd, I willa n a l y ze seve ral epistemological issues pert a i n-ing to the health theme, seeking to justify itsstatus as a scientific object. Fi n a l l y, I intend tofocus the discussion on a proposal to system-a t i ze va rious concepts of health as the initialstage for their application to the theore t i c a lc o n s t ruction of the Co l l e c t i ve Health field.

Be f o re entering into the discussion, I s h o u l dp rovide a pre l i m i n a ry semantic fra m e w o rk .The English language, the matrix for this spe-cific litera t u re, makes subtle distinctions inmeaning between the va rious concepts of dis-ease and related term s, through two semantics e ries: disease-disord e r- i l l n e s s - s i c k n e s s - m a l a-dy and impairm e n t - d i s a b i l i t y- h a n d i c a p. T h e s etwo series refer to a particular technical glos-s a ry, which due to its growing importance inc o n t e m p o ra ry scientific discourse deserve s

ALMEIDA FILHO, N.7 5 4

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

some attention in the sense of establishing at e rminological equivalence in Po rt u g u e s e, asindispensable background for participation byBrazilian re s e a rchers in this debate. T h u s, eve nwhile recognizing that such attempts can bea r b i t ra ry and incomplete, I propose to adoptthe following term i n o l o g y, which I will adhereto strictly throughout the rest of this paper: • disease = p a t o l o g i a, • d i s o rder = t ra n s t o r n o,• illness = e n f e r m i d a d e, • sickness = d o e n ç a,• malady = m o l é s t i a.

The irony of social theories of health

In the field of social sciences applied to health,since World War II there has been a somewhatinsistent search to objectively define the con-cept of disease and its correlates (Humber &A l m e d e r, 1997), with a view tow a rds form u l a t-ing “social theories of health”. This section re-views some of these pro p o s a l s, ori g i n a t i n gmainly from Anglo-Sa xon Medical So c i o l o g y.

Talcott Pa r s o n s, whose work ascribes an es-pecially central role to health phenomena foran understanding of the social system, definedillness as a “state of disturbance in the normalfunctioning of the total human individual in-cluding the organism as a biological system asmuch as its personal and social adjustment”( Parsons 1951:431). Pa r s o n’s theory of the sickrole is the first conceptual re f e rence to a seri e sof definitions of the sickness concept as a soci-etal component of the disease-illness complex,as we will see further on. Cu ri o u s l y, Pa r s o n sdoes not highlight the term d i s e a s e in his theo-ry, rather using illness and d i s o rd e r, even whenit is necessary to refer to the objective patho-logical aspects of disease (Pa r s o n s, 1951, 1964,1 9 7 5 ) .

The author later proposed to analyze He a l t has a social function, defining it as a “state of op-timum capacity for the effective performance of(socially) valued tasks” (Pa r s o n s, 1964). Pa r s o n-ian functionalist theory served as the theore t i-cal matrix for approaching individual health asa social ro l e, perf o rm a n c e, functioning, activi-t y, and capacity, among others, which we resubsequently condensed in the concept ofhealth as social well-being, a chara c t e ristic ofc o n t e m p o ra ry “quality of life” rh e t o ri c.

It is difficult to establish who was the firstauthor to systematically postulate a distinctionb e t ween disease, illness, and sickness. To justi-fy at least a semantic difference between thefirst two term s, an initial attempt was to rely on

Page 3: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

GENERAL THEORY OF HEALT H 7 5 5

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

common sense. As entries in the tra d i t i o n a lO x f o rd Di c t i o n a ry (1968), d i s e a s e means “acondition of the body, or of some part or organof the body, in which its functions are disturbedor dera n g e d” and illness is simply defined as a“quality or condition of being ill (in va r i o u ss e n s e s )”.

Field (1976) conceptualized disease as ana b n o rmality or pathological alteration re c o g-n i zed by means of a set of signs and symptomsdefined on the basis of a biomedical concep-tion. On the other hand, illness re f e r red pri-m a rily to the subjective experience of an indi-v i d u a l’s state of “ill health”, indicated by f e e l-i n g s of pain, discomfort, and malaise. Pa y i n gt ribute to the Parsonian theory of the sick ro l e,but without using the term sickness, Field ( 1 9 7 6 )f u rther contended that illness did not simplyimply a “biologically altered state”, but also tobe in a socially altered state which is seen asboth deviant and (normally) undesira b l e.

In his seminal work Causal Thinking in theHealth Sciences, Me rvyn Susser (1973) pre s e n t-ed two series of definitions that contributed lit-tle to ove rcoming the terminological confusionthen pre vailing, probably because of the limit-ed diffusion of his writings outside of the epi-demiological field. According to Susser, the t e rmdisease refers to a pathophysiological pro c e s sthat causes a state of physiological or psyc h o-logical dysfunction in the individual. On theother hand, illness is an individual, subjectives t a t e, a certain psychological and corpora la w a reness of the disease, while sickness im-plies a state of social dysfunction in the sicksubject, corresponding to Pa r s o n s’ sick ro l e.

Philosopher Christopher Boorse (1975, 1 9 7 7 )defined disease as an internal state of the bodyresulting from subnormal functioning of someof its organs or sub-systems. Some such dis-eases can evo l ve to illness if they lead to limita-tions or disabilities that meet the following cri-t e ria: (i) that they be undesirable for the sub-ject; (ii) that they be considered eligible for in-t e rventions; (iii) that they constitute a justifica-tion for normally re p roachable social behav-i o r s. Despite the clear functionalist inspira t i o n(along the Du rk h e i m - Parsons lineage), there isno special position in Bo o r s e’s original pro p o s-al for the term s i c k n e s s, while illness consti-tutes a mere subset in the order of diseases,namely those that produce psychological andsocial consequences for the individual.

Boorse subsequently stated his intent(1977) “to offer a va l u e - f ree analysis” as the ba-sis for a theoretical concept of Health, alongthe same lines as the biological concepts of lifeand death (amongst us Bra z i l i a n s, the pioneer-

ing work of Mário Chaves (1972) had alre a d yc o n c e p t u a l i zed health as an org a n i s m’s capaci-ty to function within an ecosystem re s u l t i n gf rom the Eros-Thanatos opposition, in line ofthought intriguingly similar to Bo o r s e’s pro-posal). Boorse proposed a linear art i c u l a t i o ni n volving four basic concepts: “re f e rence class”,“n o rmal function”, “d i s e a s e”, and “ h e a l t h”. T h ere f e rence class consists of the universe of m e m-bers of a biological species of the same sex andage bracket. No rmal function is defined as anindividual contribution that is “s t a t i s t i c a l l yt y p i c a l” in relation to the re f e rence class for thes p e c i e s’ surv i val and re p roduction. Disease is areduction in the “typical efficiency” invo l ved inn o rmal function. Health means simply the ab-sence of disease. Boorse completes his “ b i o s t a-tistical theory of health” with an intentionalt a u t o l o g y, indicating that health as a conceptcan simply imply norm a l i t y, always “in thesense of the absence of disease conditions”.

Co n t ra ry to the naturalist theore t i c i a n s(mainly Boorse) who believed in an objectiveand va l u e - f ree approach to health-diseasephenomena, Tristham En g e l h a rdt (1975) iden-tified a fallacy in this operation of consideri n ga b s t ract constructs as concrete things and pre-f e r red to treat them as differentiated and au-tonomous entities. T h u s, he justified the defin-ition of d i s e a s e as a scientific category destinedto explain and predict illness, suggesting thatthe latter, and not disease, was a re f e rent forhealth phenomena. In his own words (En g e l-h a rdt, 1975:137): “Commitment to the conceptof disease presupposes that there are phenome-na physical and mental which can be corre l a t e dwith events of pain and suffering, so that theirpatterns can be ex p l a i n e d , their courses pre d i c t-e d , and their outcomes influenced favo ra b l y”.

Phenomenological approaches to health( En g e l h a rdt, 1975) we re critical of natura l i s tt h e o ri e s’ objectivism. Re c e n t l y, such cri t i c i s mreached the extreme of challenging the useful-ness of the ve ry concept of disease (He s s l ow,1993), apparently with no echo among re-s e a rchers invo l ved in the important effort att h e o retical construction of the field of Me d i c a lSo c i o l o g y.

Seeking an altern a t i ve to the expanded useof the disease concept, which spawned confu-sion of both a logical and semantic ord e r, someauthors (Clouser et al., 1997; Cu l ver & Ge rt ,1982) proposed to adopt the more generic con-cept of m a l a d y. This concept supposedly de-noted the universe of categories re f e r ring todamage or threats to individual health, includ-ing both the va rious classes of disease, illness,and sickness, as well as the eve n t s, states, and

Page 4: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

ALMEIDA FILHO, N.7 5 6

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

p rocesses that we re difficult to classify as sick-ness or disease, such as disord e r, dysfunction,d e p e n d e n c y, defect, lesion, trauma, etc. De-spite the pro p o s a l’s proper intentions, the con-cept of m a l a d y has not been incorporated intoeither the theoretical discourse of the So c i o l o-gy of Health or the technical discourse of Clini-cal Me d i c i n e, and is mostly re f e r red to as a cu-riosity indicating the insufficiency of the dis-ease concept.

The Pörn - No rdenfeld theory (Pörn, 1984,1993; No rdenfeld, 1987, 1993), developed asp a rt of an effort at an economic and philo-sophical justification for Scandinavian “n e o -we l f a ri s m”, was intended to re c over a pra g m a t-ic definition of health based on updating andc o r recting Bo o r s e’s biostatistical approach. De-spite the conceptual limitations and even ac e rtain philosophical naiveté in this form u l a-tion, the proposal by Pörn (1984) is cert a i n l yi n t e resting, i.e., that the symmetrical oppositeof health is neither disease nor sickness, butrather illness (Pörn, 1984). In other word s,health is not the objective absence of disease,but the nonexistence of illness in terms ofadaptation of a human organism to a biologi-cal and social environment (Pörn, 1993).

Presenting a ve ry we l l - s t ru c t u red theore t i-cal formulation which he entitled the “p h e-nomenology of health”, No rdenfeld (1987) pro-posed a distinction between objective and sub-j e c t i ve illness which, as a logical consequenceof Pörn’s health-illness continuum, leads to them i r ror concept of “s u b j e c t i ve health”. Objectiveillness is defined by the potential functional ca-pacity not affected by the cause of the disease,while objective health corresponds to the actu-al exercise of this functional capacity. Ac c o rd-ing to this scheme, subjective illness (or non-health) has two components: (i) the aware n e s sof illness (in the author’s word s, the “m e re be-lief or awareness that someone is ill”) and (ii)the feeling of illness (or the “set of mentalstates associated with illness”). T h u s, as postu-lated by No rdenfeld, a person P is subjective l yhealthy if and only if he/she (1) is not subjec-t i vely ill, (2) believes that he/she is healthy, or(3) is not experiencing a mental state associat-ed with some currently existing objective ill-ness (No rdenfeld, 1987, 1993).

Along this same line, Fu l f o rd (1994) con-tends that not even the concept of disease isva l u e - f re e, defending a pragmatic appro a c ht h rough the use of two different levels of analy-s i s, one descri p t i ve and the other interpre t a-t i ve. Gi ven that the former level incorpora t e sdisease concepts in which a high degree of c o n-sensus pre va i l s, according to Fu l f o rd it is nec-

e s s a ry to focus more on the latter analyticall e vel. In this case, disease concepts could be re-f e r red to generically as “f a i l u re s”. Disease w o u l dc o r respond to a “role failure”, while illnesswould result from an “action failure”. Fi n a l l y,Fu l f o rd (1994) challenges the existence of a de-t e rministic link between disease and illness, aspostulated by the majority of the authors re-v i e wed, indicating that the actual illness expe-rience cannot be explained by disease con-c e p t s, that rather it must be understood asphenomenologically give n .

Re c e n t l y, Boorse (1997) self-critically ad-mitted the need to ove rcome his negative - e vo-l u t i ve concept of health (based on the dysfunc-tion-disease-illness gradient), proposing to re-place it with the notion of “d e g rees of health”.This entails an extremely narrow definition ofp o s i t i ve health as the maximum possible de-g ree of health as opposed to any reduction inoptimum normal function for the re f e re n c ec l a s s. Ac c o rding to this concept, normality hast h ree levels of specification: theoretically nor-mal, diagnostically normal, and thera p e u t i c a l-ly normal. The logical opposite of the diseaseconcept would be theoretical (or conceptual)n o rm a l i t y. The re s p e c t i ve antagonists would fitwith the other levels of norm a l i t y: diagnostical-ly abnormal and therapeutically abnormal. Fi-n a l l y, Boorse analyzes the extreme situations of“ i l l n e s s” (as opposed to “we l l n e s s”) and death-l i f e. The underlying relationships of belongingand opposition in this interesting scheme arefound in Fi g u re 1. Cu riously enough, the essen-tial fra m e w o rk of this proposal had also alre a d ybeen laid out in the study by Mário Chave s(1972) quoted above.

A partial inve n t o ry is in order at this point.To begin, nearly all of the authors and schoolsre v i e wed thus far present proposals marked bya predominantly biological frame of re f e re n c e.T h e re f o re, they almost inevitably lead to theo-ries not of Health, but of pathological pro c e s s-es and their corre l a t e s, in which Health is nec-e s s a rily seen as the absence of sickness. Co n s e-q u e n t l y, one observes an emphasis on the sub-individual and individual leve l s, where patho-logical and experiential processes actually oc-c u r. This chain of logical omissions, entailing areduced focus on the concept of sickness andthe sick role impedes a collective conceptual-ization of Health (except, of course, as the sumof individual absences of disease). He re we finda flagrant iro n y: despite the promising Pa r s o n-ian debut, Medical Sociology has not proven ca-pable of constructing a social theory of health.

Page 5: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

GENERAL THEORY OF HEALT H 7 5 7

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

A n t h ropological models of disease-illness-sickness

This section expounds on the issue of health-disease models from the interpre t a t i ve per-s p e c t i ve of contempora ry Medical Anthro p o l o-g y, conve rging on a proposal integrating theconcepts of disease, illness, and sickness.

A rthur Kleinman, Leon Ei s e n b e rg, and By-ron Good (Kleinman et al., 1978), seeking toe n rich the analysis of non-biological compo-nents of health-disease phenomena, system-a t i zed in 1978 a model that ascribed specialt h e o retical importance to the notion of “s i c k-n e s s”, emphasizing the social and cultural as-pects that had para d oxically been ove r l o o k e dby previous sociological appro a c h e s. (Cu ri o u s-l y, Kleinman and his disciples omitted pri o rconceptual deve l o p m e n t s, even those occur-ring within the field of social sciences in healthas discussed in the previous section). This pro-posal was based on the distinction between bi-ological and cultural dimensions of sickness,c o r responding to two categories: disease andi l l n e s s. The model is shown schematically inFi g u re 2, highlighting the implicitly negativedefinition of health as the absence of sickness.

From this perspective, the pathologicalfunctioning of organs or physiological systemsoccurs re g a rdless of its recognition or perc e p-tion by the individual or social enviro n m e n t .Within a frame of re f e rence that is quite con-g ruent with Bo o r s e’s theory, according to Klein-man (Kleinman, 1980, 1986; Kleinman et al.,1978), disease refers to alterations or dysfunc-tion in biological and/or psychological p ro c e s s-e s, as defined by the biomedical concept. Onthe other hand, the illness category incorpo-rates individual experience and perception vis-à-vis both the problems deriving from the dis-ease and social reaction tow a rds illness. T h econcept of illness thus relates to processes ofsignifying sickness. In addition to their cultura laspects, meanings also touch on particular s y m-bolic aspects forming the illness itself withinthe individual psychological sphere, as well asthe meanings created by the patient whiledealing with the disease process (Massé, 1995).

Su b s e q u e n t l y, Kleinman (1988, 1992) par-tially re v i e wed his original objectivist position,contending that both disease and illness aresocial constru c t s. Illness means the way sickindividuals perc e i ve, expre s s, and deal with thep rocess of becoming ill. Illness is thus prior tos i c k n e s s, which is produced on the basis of atechnical re c o n s t ruction of professional dis-course in the physician-patient encounter,t h rough communication around the cultura l l y

s h a red language of sickness. Ac c o rding to thissame author (Kleinman, 1980), health, illness,and care are parts of a cultural system, and assuch they should be understood through theirmutual re l a t i o n s. To examine them separa t e l yd i s t o rts our understanding of both their re-s p e c t i ve chara c t e ristics and the way they func-tion in a given context.

Kleinman (1986) further proposed that oneof the reasons that different healing pro c e s s e spersist within the same society is because theyact on different dimensions of sickness. T h u s,one must consider different models capable ofconceiving health and illness as resulting fro mthe complex interaction among multiple fac-tors at the biological, psychological, and socio-logical leve l s, with a terminology not limited tob i o m e d i c i n e. In order to construct such mod-e l s, one must turn to new interd i s c i p l i n a ry

D e a t h

S i c k n e s s

Therapeutic abnorm a l i t y Therapeutic norm a l i t y

Diagnosed abnorm a l i t y Diagnosed norm a l i t y

T h e o retical norm a l i t yD i s e a s e

Positive healthSub-optimal health

We l l n e s s

L i f e

F i g u re 1

B o o r s e ’s degrees of health model.

Sickness: disease + illness

d i s e a s e

H E A LT H S I C K N E S S

i l l n e s s

F i g u re 2

Kleinman & Good model.

Page 6: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

ALMEIDA FILHO, N.7 5 8

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

m e t h o d s, working simultaneously with ethno-g raphic, clinical, epidemiological, histori c a l ,social, political, economic, technological, andp s ychological data.

By ron Good & Ma ry- Jo Good (1980, 1982),re i n f o rcing the perspective of intra- and inter-c u l t u ral relativism in illness, postulated thatthe borders between normal/pathological andhealth/disease are established by illness expe-riences in different culture s, through the waysby which they are narrated, and by the ri t u a l se m p l oyed to re c o n s t ruct the world that suffer-ing destroy s. From this perspective, sickness(and by extension, health) is not a thing in it-self, or even a re p resentation of such a thing,but an object resulting from this intera c t i o n ,capable of synthesizing multiple meanings.

Good & Good (1980) proposed a “c u l t u ra lhermeneutic model” to understand We s t e rnmedical ra t i o n a l i t y. Ac c o rding to these authors,the interpretation of symptoms as a manifesta-tion of the underlying “biological reality” isc h a ra c t e ristic of clinical reasoning, since thelatter is based epistemologically on an empiri-cist theory of language (Good & Good, 1980).Ac c o rding to the biomedical health-diseasemodel, clinical practice is supported by know l-edge of causal chains operating at the biologi-cal level, following a script for decoding the pa-t i e n t’s complaints in order to identify the un-derlying somatic or psychological pathologicalp ro c e s s. T h u s, the model has a double objec-t i ve: to establish the disease diagnosis and top ropose effective and rational treatment. Ac-c o rding to Good & Good (1982), ascri b i n g“symptom meaning” to an altered physiologi-cal state proves insufficient as a basis for clini-cal pra c t i c e, since psychological, social, andc u l t u ral factors influence the experience ofs i c k n e s s, its manifestation, and the expre s s i o nof symptoms.

One of the central points in this “c ritical re-f o rm” process in medical knowledge consistsof the distinction between disease and illness.A g reeing with Kleinman, Good & Good (1982)re a f f i rm that the disease process correlates w i t hor is caused by biological and/or psyc h o l o g i c a la l t e ra t i o n s, while illness is situated in the do-main of language and meaning and there f o reconstitutes a human experi e n c e. Ac c o rding tothese authors, illness is fundamentally seman-tic, and the tra n s f o rmation of disease into ahuman experience and an object of medical at-tention occurs through a process of attri b u t i o nof meaning. T h u s, not only illness but also dis-ease constitute a cultural construct, in this casebased on theory and webs of significance com-p rising the different medical sub-culture s.

Meaning is not the product of a closed re l a-tionship between signifier and the thing (in thesense of an objective reality in the physical uni-verse), but of a network of symbols constru c t-ed in the interpre t a t i ve act, which they refer toas a “semantic network” (Good & Good, 1982).Illness becomes an experience with meaningfor each particular individual. Even so, it is im-p o rtant to consider the relationship betwe e nindividual meanings and the network of mean-ings inherent to each broader cultural contextto which individuals belong. T h e rein lies thenotion of illness as a “n e t w o rk of significance”,in the sense of a reality constructed through ap rocess of interpretation/signification, basedon the plot of meanings that stru c t u res the cul-t u re itself and its va rious sub-culture s. Sy m p-t o m s, full of at least individual meanings, allowaccess to biomedicine’s web of significance,that is, culturally established disease signs inthe form of a “s y n d rome of meanings” (Good &Good, 1980).

In an attempt to develop an approach tothe determination of sickness in societies b a s e don analysis of social relations of pro d u c t i o n ,Allan Young (1980, 1982) presents a critique ofsickness models as proposed by Kleinman andGood & Good. On the one hand, he postulatesthat the Kleinman-Good model only sees theindividual as object and arena for significante vents re g a rding illness, failing to re p o rt theways by which social relations form and dis-t ribute it. On the other hand, while acknow l-edging the Kleinman-Good model’s adva n c e sover the biomedical model, Young contendsthat the distinction between disease and illnessis insufficient to explain the social dimensionsof the process of becoming ill.

To ove rcome these limitations, Young ( 1 9 8 0 )proposes to replace the Kleinman-Good s c h e m e[sickness = disease + illness] with a triple seri e sof categories (sickness, illness, and disease)with equivalent hiera rchical leve l s, albeit g ra n t-ing greater theoretical re l e vance to the “s i c k-n e s s” component. It is in this sense that Yo u n gends up postulating an “a n t h ropology of sick-n e s s” (Young, 1982). He rein, I propose to desig-nate the Young model as DIS Complex (dise a s e -illness-sickness), as re p resented in Fi g u re 3.

Ac c o rding to Young (1982), although Klein-man emphasizes the social determinants of thee x p l a n a t o ry models and Good highlights thep ower relations in medical discourses and p ra c-t i c e s, neither actually undertakes an analysis ofthese aspects in their work. Ac c o rding to Yo u n g ,medical practices display an important politi-cal and ideological component, based on pow-er relations that justify unequal distribution of

Page 7: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

GENERAL THEORY OF HEALT H 7 5 9

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

illness and tre a t m e n t s, as well as their conse-q u e n c e s. T h e re f o re, the elements of the DISComplex (disease-illness-sickness) complexa re not neutral term s, but rather entail a circ u-lar process by which biological and behaviora lsigns are socially signified as symptoms. T h e s es y m p t o m s, in turn, are interpreted by way of asemeiology that associates them with cert a i netiologies and that justify interventions whoseresults end up legitimating them as diagnosticsigns of certain diseases. The author furt h e rcomments that in pluralistic medical systems,a set of signs can designate different illnessesand therapeutic practices that fail to ove r l a p.Social forces are what determine which indi-viduals suffer certain illnesses, display cert a i ns i c k n e s s e s, and have access to given tre a t-m e n t s. Depending on the sick individual’s so-cioeconomic position, the same disease canimply different illnesses and sicknesses andd i f f e rent healing pro c e s s e s.

Ac c o rding to Young (1980, 1982), the con-cept of sickness should incorporate the pro c e s sof ascribing socially acknowledged meaningsto signs of deviant behaviors and biological sig-n a l s, tra n s f o rming them into socially signifi-cant symptoms and eve n t s. In his own word s,“Sickness is a process for socializing disease andi l l n e s s” ( Young, 1982:270). This process of so-cializing disease – or better still, of social con-s t ruction of sickness – occurs in part withinand through medical systems, linked to soci-e t y ’s broader ideological circ u i t s. Young statesthat this ideological dimension, through differ-ent forms of health knowledge and pra c t i c e, re-p roduces specific views of the social order andacts to maintain them. In the final analysis,re p resentations of sickness constitute elementsin the mystification of its social origin and socialconditions in the production of know l e d g e. Ac-cording to Young (1980), the translation of formsof suffering (illness) deri ved from class re l a-tions in medical terms constitutes a neutra l i z a-tion process following the interests of the hege-monic classes. That is, through the medicaliza-tion pro c e s s, the ill condition is reduced to theindividual biological level, failing to considerits social, political, and historical dimensions.

Indeed, the focus on sickness supplants theemphasis on the individual or micro-social lev-els (chara c t e ristic of Kleinman’s approach, forexample). Howe ve r, although it is an import a n tstep forw a rd over its pre d e c e s s o r s, Yo u n g’s DISComplex opens only one possibility for incor-p o rating the Health issue: once again the mereabsence of disease-illness-sickness.

In conclusion, one should value the effortat drafting a general theory of health-disease-

c a re, a badge of the intellectual undertaking ofthese distinguished heirs to the applied an-t h ropology of the 1970s. Even considering thei m p o rtance ascribed to patients’ beliefs andc u l t u ral and personal meanings, as well as thep roposal for integrating va rious components ofhealth care systems and their re s p e c t i ve ex-p l a n a t o ry models, the view of these theore t i-cians tow a rds the conceptual issue of Health isnot sufficiently tra n s d i s c i p l i n a ry to broaden thescope of the medical anthropological appro a c h ,re s t ricted to the view of Health as absence of ill-n e s s. The Kleinman-Good and Young models ac-tually remain constrained to cura t i ve pra c t i c e s,focusing on the ill individual’s re t u rn to norm a lfunctioning and healthy life, without even en-t e ring into the definition of normality or actual-ly analyzing if the Health concept fits into it.

Semeiologic approaches to health-disease-care

Re c e n t l y, Good (1994) developed a critical se-meiologic perspective for the analysis of h e a l t h -disease models, re e valuating the semantic net-w o rk concept, identifying two limitations to it:

The first relates to the redefinition of theDIS Complex in light of linguistic theory, give nthe insufficiency of the perspective accord i n gto which a symbol condenses multiple mean-i n g s. Ac c o rding to Good, one must re c o g n i zethe diversity of national, ethnic, re l i g i o u s, andp rofessional languages in the contempora ryworld, as well as the multiplicity of vo i c e s, the

D i s e a s e I l l n e s s

S i c k n e s s

H E A LT H

H E A LT H H E A LT H

DIS Complex( D i s e a s e - I l l n e s s - S i c k n e s s )

F i g u re 3

Young model.

Page 8: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

ALMEIDA FILHO, N.7 6 0

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

individuality of these vo i c e s, in short, an i n t e r-dialogue and an a l t e r-dialogue present in thec o n s t ruction of discourses on health-disease.Illness is not only constituted by the individualpoint of view, but by multiple and fre q u e n t l yconflicting pathways; in this sense it is dialog-i c. Even while illness is synthesized in familiarn a r ra t i ve s, loaded with gender and kinshipp o l i c i e s, it is also (and now as disease) objecti-fied as a specific form of physiological disord e rin case presentations and conversations a m o n gp h y s i c i a n s, even if these objectification can bes u bve rted or resisted by patients. Sickness isimmersed in a social web in which eve ryo n enegotiates the constitution of the medical ob-ject and the guidance of the material body.

The second limitation to the analysis of se-mantic networks refers to the reduced possibil-ity of re p resenting the diversity of forms of au-t h o rity and resistance associated with the med-ical system’s central elements. Semantic net-w o rk s, albeit produced by power and authori t ys t ru c t u re s, can provide the necessary means tounderstand how hegemonic forms are org a-n i zed and re p roduced, since they are cultura l l yrooted and sustain discourses and pra c t i c e s.Howe ve r, Good (1994) acknowledges that thisrelationship between semantic stru c t u res andhegemonic power relations has not been suffi-ciently developed by the main authors in thist h e o retical field, as maintained by Yo u n g’s ra d-ical cri t i q u e.

The notion of semantic network should t h u sbe expanded to indicate that the meaning ofsickness is not univocal, but the product of in-t e rc o n n e c t i o n s. It is no longer just a syndro m eof meanings, but also a syndrome of experi-e n c e s, word s, feelings, and actions invo l v i n gd i f f e rent members of society. This set of ele-ments is condensed in the essential symbols ofthe medical lexicon, implying that such dive r-sity can be culturally synthesized and objecti-fied. Semantic networks constitute deep stru c-t u res that link illness to a culture’s fundamen-tal va l u e s, meanwhile remaining outside of theexplicit cultural knowledge and awareness ofthe society’s members, presenting themselve sas natural. This new analytical agenda for se-mantic networks (Good, 1994) treats the DISComplex as a narra t i ve, both natural and cul-t u ral, resulting from concre t e, partially inde-t e rminate sickness pro c e s s e s, a ve ritable scri p tm a rked by a plot with different perspective s.

Ad vancing such critical perspective, Gi l l e sBibeau and Ellen Co rin state that contempo-ra ry cultural anthro p o l o g y, through its inter-p re t a t i ve and phenomenological watersheds,has proven incapable of dealing with the com-

plexity of health and sickness pro c e s s e s. T h i sn e c e s s a rily results from the emphasis on thestudy of subjective experiences in falling ill andthe reification of sickness narra t i ve s, taken asautonomous texts, without ever establishingrelations with either the ove rall sociocultura lcontext or the disease’s “o b j e c t i ve” dimension.Despite emphasizing the importance of cultur-al values and the influence of the semantic net-w o rk concept in their work, Bibeau, Co rin, andc o l l a b o rators (Almeida Filho et al., unpub-lished manuscript; Bibeau, 1988, 1994; Bi b e a u& Co rin, 1994, 1995; Co rin, 1995; Co rin et al.,1993; Co rin & Lauzon, 1992; INECOM, 1993)re a f f i rm the need for a macro-social and his-t o rical approach to understand local contexts.This means establishing an epistemological,t h e o retical, and methodological connectionb e t ween different dimensions of re a l i t y, art i c u-lating a meta-synthetic theory or “global per-s p e c t i ve” (Bibeau, 1988) intended to integra t eessential semeiologic, interpre t a t i ve, and pra g-matic elements for a cultural model of health-d i s e a s e - c a re. In the particular sphere of health,the issue is to explore the relations between se-meiologic systems of meanings and extern a lconditions for production (the economic-po-litical context and its historical determ i n a t i o n )and the experience of falling ill (Co rin, 1995).

Seeking to analyze the issue of different lev-els of determination in health phenomena,these authors (Bibeau, 1994; Bibeau & Co ri n ,1994; Corin, 1995) propose an analytical s c h e m ebased on two central categories: collective s t ru c-t u ring conditions and organizing experi e n c e s.Using these concepts, they intend to re p re s e n tthe different contextual (social and cultural) el-ements that link to form the systems of socialresponses tow a rds “s t ru c t u ral pathogenic de-v i c e s”. The stru c t u ring conditions encompassthe macro-context, that is, environmental con-s t ra i n t s, political power network s, economicd e velopment para m e t e r s, historical legacies,and daily conditions of existence (or modes oflife). In other word s, it is a matter of condition-ing factors acting to modulate culture and limitfunctional freedom of action at the species andindividual leve l s. Co l l e c t i ve organizing experi-e n c e s, in turn, re p resent the elements in theg ro u p’s socio-symbolic universe that act tomaintain the gro u p’s identity, value systems,and social organization (Bibeau, 1988). T h u s,by postulating that semeiologic systems andmodes of production link to produce the expe-rience of falling ill, the authors re t ri e ve Yo u n g’sintent to consider the socioeconomic, political,and historical context in health-disease-carep ro c e s s e s.

Page 9: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

GENERAL THEORY OF HEALT H 7 6 1

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

From this perspective, Bibeau and Co rin ef-f e c t i vely point to an o u ve rt u re of meaning inthe health field, implying a new view of the DISComplex. They propose understanding thefalling-ill process as based on the above - m e n-tioned “global perspective”, linking individualt ra j e c t o ri e s, cultural codes, the macro - s o c i a lcontext, and historical determination. To thisend, they advance an anthropological, semeio-logic, and phenomenological theoretical f ra m e-w o rk to study local systems of signification andaction vis-à-vis health pro b l e m s. Such systemsa re rooted in the gro u p’s social dynamics andc e n t ral cultural values underlying the individ-ual construction of the falling-ill experi e n c eand collective construction of the social pro-duction of sickness (Bibeau, 1994; Bibeau &Co rin, 1994, 1995; Co rin, 1995).

In the communities’ spheres of symbolicp roduction, corporal, linguistic, and behav-i o ral signs are tra n s f o rmed into symptoms of ag i ven illness, acquiring specific causal mean-ings and generating given social re a c t i o n s,shaping what Bibeau & Co rin (Bibeau & Co ri n ,1994) propose to call the “system of signs,m e a n i n g s, and practices of health” (SmpH). Ing e n e ral, locally constructed popular know l-edge is plural, fragmented, and even contra d i c-t o ry. Popular semeiology and cultural modelsof interpretation do not exist as an explicitbody of know l e d g e, but are formed by a va ri e dset of imaginary and symbolic elements, ri t u a l-i zed as rational. Ac c o rding to these authors,popular knowledge about Health and its coun-t e r p a rts (expressed in the DIS Complex) arelinked and expressed in terms of socially andh i s t o rically constructed SmpH systems.

SmpH systems thus shape a popular se-meiology of health problems in context. To ap-p roach them systematically or “s c i e n t i f i c a l l y ”,the authors propose to look beyond the pro f e s-sional diagnostic cri t e ria of the biomedicalmodel and document the particular cases com-p rising actual cultural va riations (Almeida Fi l-ho et al., unpublished manuscript; Bibeau &Co rin, 1994, 1995; Co rin, 1995). In the dailyp rocess of defining categories and re c o g n i z i n gcases in these categori e s, “o rd i n a ry” people(the community, according to Bibeau & Co ri n )do not necessarily function by identifyingc l e a r-cut categories of thought, but by perc e i v-ing similarities and analogies and establishinga continuity among cases according to a ri c hand fluctuating range of cri t e ria (Almeida Fi l h oet al., unpublished manuscript; Bibeau & Co ri n ,1994, 1995; Co rin, 1995). Component categ o ri e sof SmpH systems are fragmented, contra d i c t o-ry, partially shared, locally constructed, org a-

n i zed in multiple semantic and pra x e o l o g i c a lsystems (i.e., stru c t u red in practices), in histor-ical context, and accessible only through con-c rete situations – eve n t s, behaviors, and narra-t i ve s. This mode of categorization refers to ob-ject-models formed by “Lakoff pro t o t y p e s” in-stead of hiera rchical classifications of discre t e,mutually exc l u s i ve, and stable categori e s, typi-fied by formally consistent logic. The conceptof “p ro t o t y p e”, key to linguist Ge o rge Lakoff’st h e o ry (Lakoff, 1993), implies categories of flu-id, imprecise meanings with re l a t i ve degrees ofs t a b i l i t y, discriminated by fuzzy limits in defin-ition. Because they differ from the categori c a llogic pre vailing in We s t e rn, Aristotelian think-ing, Lakoff prototypes can be better under-stood through altern a t i ve systems like Za d e h’sfuzzy logic (as suggested by Lakoff himself ) orNewton da Co s t a’s para-consistent logic (Co s-ta, 1989).

The theory is still being constructed and isthus quite incomplete, full of gaps and incon-s i s t e n c i e s. Co n t ra ry to the approaches dis-cussed earlier, the SmpH theory unhesitatinglyp resents itself as the basis for a Ge n e ral T h e o ryof Health. Ne ve rt h e l e s s, even in an indirect andattenuated way, this theory is still centered oni l l n e s s, justified as such by the observation thatpopular semeiology is also stru c t u red on theconcept of sickness and its corre l a t e s. On theother hand, by considering the biological fieldunderlying the DIS Complex only in a part i a land fragmented way, the SmpH approach ru n sthe risk of stru c t u ring itself abstractly as a kindof anti-naturalism, pri o ritizing social, cultura l ,and linguistic aspects of sickness over the ma-t e rial and objective elements of disease, cap-tured by modern medical technology. Of c o u r s e,taking medical knowledge and clinical pra c t i c eas cultural constructs (which they actually are ) ,and consequently as objects of anthro p o l o g i c a li n q u i ry, does not shift the material basis ofh e a l t h - d i s e a s e - c a re processes and phenome-na. This theory merely outlines a broad defini-tion of “s t ru c t u ral pathogenic devices” by de-veloping an analysis of different opera t i o n a ll e vels in the SmpH systems re s t ricted to local-global and social micro - m a c ro polari t i e s, char-a c t e ristic of contempora ry anthropological de-b a t e. Any heuristically efficient treatment ofthe Health issue will certainly have to anchor itin more complex explanatory models andb roader conceptual spectra: that of the molec-u l a r-subindividual-systemic-ecological in thebiological dimension and of the individual-g ro u p - s o c i e t a l - c u l t u ral in the historical di-m e n s i o n .

Page 10: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

ALMEIDA FILHO, N.7 6 2

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

The epistemology of Health

What has been discussed thus far appears toshape a certain chronicle of a concept’s re s i s-t a n c e. “He a l t h” is certainly not a docile or sub-m i s s i ve object of analysis. It has resisted moreor less competent attempts at domesticationby the sciences of both stru c t u re and interpre-tation. A critical inve n t o ry of this effort leadsone to conclude that the social and anthro p o-logical scientific approach to the Health issuehas reached its limits, proving incapable ofdealing with the pro p e rties of the object-mod-el it intends to construct. But is the quest for aGe n e ral T h e o ry of Health really feasible, takingthe health concept as a given object-model? Ins h o rt, can health be treated as a scientific con-cept? Or, does this undertaking entail an un-derlying philosophical problem or some essen-tial epistemological obstacle? If it is possible toc o n c e i ve of Health as a concept, how can epis-temology contribute to the effort? This sectionis intended to evaluate this set of questions.

Without a doubt, the nature of Health con-stitutes a secular philosophical question, per-haps of the magnitude of Ru s s e l l’s para d ox orHu m e’s pro b l e m s. De s c a rtes identified it andKant later systematized it as a basic pro b l e mfor philosophy (Canguilhem, 1990). T h e re f o relet us call it Ka n t’s Pro b l e m .

Among the contempora ry philosopherswho have focused on the Health issue, Ge o rg e sCanguilhem deserves special attention. In hisi n a u g u ral work Le Normal et le Pa t o l o g i q u e(1978), Canguilhem indicated that the medicaldefinition of normality stems largely fro mp h y s i o l o g y, founding a positivity that impedesviewing sickness as a new form of life. T h e re-f o re, disease could not be admitted as an ob-j e c t i ve datum, given that positivist scientificmethods only have the ability to define va ri-eties or differe n c e s, without any positive orn e g a t i ve vital va l u e.

From this perspective, the normality-p a t h o l-ogy and health-disease conceptual dyads arenot symmetrical or equivalent, to the extentthat normal and pathological do not constitutec o n t ra ry or contra d i c t o ry concepts. Pa t h o l o g i-cal does not mean the absence of norm s, butthe presence of other vitally inferior norm s,which pre vent the individual from experi e n c-ing the same mode of life allowed to healthy in-d i v i d u a l s. He n c e, for Canguilhem, pathologicalc o r responds directly to the concept of sick, im-plying the vital opposite of healthy. Po s s i b i l i-ties in the state of health are superior to nor-mal capacities: health constitutes a certain ca-pacity to ove rcome the crises determined by

the forces of disease to install a new physiolog-ical ord e r.

Re p resenting a histori o g raphic watershedin the Canguilhemian theory of the norm a l -pathological tension, Michel Foucault (1963,1976) sought to indicate how new standards ofn o rmality emerged in the sphere of genera land psyc h i a t ric medicine. In the context of1 8 t h - c e n t u ry cultural re c o n s t ruction, attemptswe re made to intervene in human individuals,their bodies, their minds, and not only in thephysical environment, to there by norm a l i ze itfor production. To list the normal possibilitiesfor human yields and capacities, as well as thep a rameters for normal social functioning, be-came the task of psyc h i a t ric medicine, psy-c h o l o g y, and applied social sciences. From thisp e r s p e c t i ve, the implicit concepts in Fo u c a u l t’sw o rk re veal his adherence to a definition ofhealth as an adaptive capacity (or submission)to disciplinary powe r s.

Su b s e q u e n t l y, Canguilhem (1966) statedthat normality as a life norm constitutes ab roader category, encompassing healthy andpathological as distinct sub-categori e s. In thiss e n s e, both health and sickness are normal, tothe extent that both imply a certain life norm ,w h e re health is a superior life norm and sick-ness is an inferior one. Health is no longer lim-ited to the perspective of adaptation, no longeru n re s t ricted obedience to the established m o d-el. It is more than this, to the extent that it canconstitute itself precisely by non-obedienceand tra n s f o rmation. Ac c o rding to the elderCanguilhem (1966, 1990), health as the perf e c tabsence of sickness is situated in the field ofd i s e a s e. The threshold between health andsickness is singular, although influenced byf o rces that transcend the strictly individual,like the cultural, socioeconomic, and politicalg rounds (Caponi, 1997). In the final analysis,the influence of these contexts occurs at the in-dividual level. Ne ve rt h e l e s s, this influence doesnot directly determine the result (health or s i c k-ness) of this interaction, to the extent that itseffects are subordinated to norm a t i ve pro c e s s-es of symbolization.

Canguilhem systematizes his reflections onhealth in a little-known lecture given at theUn i versity of St ra s b o u rg in 1988 and publishedin a limited edition (Canguilhem, 1990). In thisp a p e r, after a brief etymological analysis, re f e r-ring back to Hi p p o c ratic ideas, Ca n g u i l h e mnotes that over the course of history, healthwas treated as if it could not be grasped by re a-son and thus did not belong to the scientificfield. He dwells particularly on the philosopherKant, who, as we have seen, provided the basis

Page 11: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

GENERAL THEORY OF HEALT H 7 6 3

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

to position health as an object outside of thefield of know l e d g e, where by it could never be ascientific concept, but rather a commonplace,popular notion, within eve ryo n e’s reach.

The idea that health is something individ-ual, pri va t e, unique, and subjective has re c e n t-ly been defended by the eminent philosopherHa n s - Ge o rg Ga d a m e r, one of the main expo-nents of contempora ry hermeneutics (Ga d a-m e r, 1996). Ac c o rding to Ga d a m e r, the mysteryof health lies in its elliptic, enigmatic chara c t e r.Health does not present itself to individuals. Itcannot be measured, because it entails an in-t e rnal agreement and cannot be controlled bye x t e rnal forc e s. Gadamer goes so far as to saythat the mystery of health is equivalent to them y s t e ry of life. In his opinion, the distinctionb e t ween health and illness cannot be clearlydefined. The distinction is pragmatic, and canonly be accessed by the person who feels illand who, no longer capable of dealing with thedemands of life and the fear of death, decidesto visit the doctor. Ga d a m e r’s conclusion (Ga-d a m e r, 1996) is simple: due to its pri va t e, per-sonal, radically subjective nature, health cann e ver be reduced to an object of science.

Canguilhem (1990) would agree that healthis a philosophical issue to the extent that it es-capes the reach of instru m e n t s, pro t o c o l s, andscientific equipment, since it is defined as fre eand unconditional. This “philosophical health”would cove r, but not be confused with, individ-ual, pri va t e, and subjective health. It is a phe-nomenon without a concept, emerging fro mthe praxeological relationship in the physician-patient encounter, validated exc l u s i vely by thesick subject and his/her physician. Clinicalk n owledge is attributed to the mission of apply-ing a technology and practice of protecting thiss u b j e c t i ve, individual health. Yet philosophicalhealth does not only incorporate individualhealth, but also its complement, re c o g n i z a b l eas a public health (i.e., a health made public).

The philosopher’s notion of public health,re f e r ring to ethical and metaphysical questions(which would result for example in the notionsof utility, quality of life, and happiness), move saway from the public health expert’s conceptof health, which understands the state of h e a l t hof populations and its determ i n a n t s, both inthe sense of a complement to the epidemiolog-ical concept of risk and as a re f e rence to theb roader concept of the radical need for health.The concept of radical need comes from thep o s t - Ma rxist Hu n g a rian philosopher AgnesHeller (1986), providing an especially intere s t-ing conceptual opening for a Ge n e ral T h e o ry ofHealth endeavo r, to the extent that it implies

health as something positive, albeit in the par-tial sense of filling an essential lack or need in asubject (like resistance or resilience) or society(as a positive health situation) (Paim, 1996).This proposal was applied to the health field byR i c a rdo Bruno Go n ç a l ve s, according to whom“health needs could be conceptualized as whatmust be achieved for a being to continue to be ab e i n g” (Go n ç a l ve s, 1992:19) – I owe this obser-vation to Ja i rnilson Paim (personal communi-c a t i o n ) .

Canguilhem (1990) is against the exc l u s i o nof health as an object of the scientific field, an-ticipating a stance contra ry to that of Ga d a m e r.He contends that health is re a l i zed in the geno-t y p e, in the subject’s life history, and in the in-d i v i d u a l’s relationship to the enviro n m e n t ;h e n c e, the idea of a philosophical health wouldnot preclude taking health as a scientific ob-ject. While philosophical health would encom-pass individual health, scientific health wouldbe public health, that is, a healthiness consti-tuted in opposition to the idea of morbidity.Since the body is the product of complexp rocesses of exchange with the enviro n m e n t ,to the extent that these processes can con-t ribute to determine the phenotype, healthwould correspond to an implied order both inthe biological sphere of life and the mode oflife (Canguilhem, 1990). As a product/effect ofa given mode of life, health implies a feeling ofbeing able to confront the force of illness, thusfunctioning as a sort of openness tow a rds so-cial ri s k s, as analyzed by Caponi (1997).

At this stage of his argument, Ca n g u i l h e mrefers to Hy g i e n e, which begins as a tra d i t i o n a lmedical discipline, made of norm s, not dis-guising its political ambition of regulating thel i ves of individuals. Beginning with Hy g i e n e,health becomes an object of calculation andbegins to lose its dimension as a pri vate tru t h ,receiving an empirical meaning as a set and ef-fect of objective pro c e s s e s. Canguilhem (1990)insists that health is not only life in the silenceof the org a n s, as affirmed by Leri c h e, but alsolife in the silence of social re l a t i o n s. It is fro mthis perspective that we can insert the dis-course of collective health as we know it. Ye tCanguilhem (1990) contends after all that sci-entific health could also assimilate some as-pects of individual, subjective, philosophicalhealth, so that not only sickness and healthi-ness (or, using a more up-to-date term i n o l o g y,the risks) should be studied by science. Fi g u re4 is an attempt at schematically depicting theCaguilhemian position on this issue.

It is curious to note that Canguilhem hada l ready taken a stance on this question long

Page 12: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

ALMEIDA FILHO, N.7 6 4

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

b e f o re. On the one hand, he re c o g n i zes thehealth concept’s potentially scientific quality,since even admitting that this does not refer toan existence, rather to a norm with functionand va l u e, “this does not mean that health is anempty concept” (Canguilhem, 1978:54). On theother hand, young Canguilhem finds no justifi-cation for a specific health science endeavo r, atleast at the individual level. In his own word s :“If health is life in the silence of the organs, t h e reis no science of health per se. Health is organici n n o c e n c e . And it must be lost, like all inno-c e n c e , in order for knowledge to become possi-b l e” (Canguilhem, 1978:76).

In this same sense, the radically phenome-nological Ga d a m e rian perspective in defenseof pri va t e, subjective, inherently enigmatichealth would justify ruling out the feasibility ofa scientific approach to health. Howe ve r, I seeas a para d ox the fact that one of Ga d a m e r’smain proposals (Ga d a m e r, 1996) turns out tobe crucial for the advancement of an altern a-t i ve formulation for the scientific object ofhealth. Based on an etymological argument, asis his style, he defends the idea that health isinescapably all-encompassing, because its c o n-cept directly indicates wholeness or totality.From this angle, the Ga d a m e rian notion of the“health enigma” ends up opening the way for a

synthetic (or meta-synthetic, as we shall see l a t-er) approach to the scientific concept of health.

The Argentine epistemologist Juan Sa m a j a ,author of the classic Epistemología y Me t o d o-logía (Samaja, 1994), a rare case of a philosopherwith training and interest in Public Health, takesCanguilhem as his point of depart u re to inve s t i-gate the conditions allowing for a scientific the-o ry of health. Samaja (1997) cri t i c i zes both theCanguilhemian premise that the health conceptis concerned fundamentally with the biologicalworld and the implicit Foucaultian pre m i s ethat proposes a purely social or merely discur-s i ve (ideological-political) concept of health.

Ac c o rding to Samaja (1997), the para d i g mof Complex Ad a p t i ve Systems could serve asthe epistemological basis for ove rcoming thebiological-social antinomy, given conceptualdemands already established by the deve l o p-ment and practical use of the “ h e a l t h” notionin modern lay and technical discourses. In hisopinion, one must conceive of the health con-cept as an object with distinct hiera rc h i c a lf a c e t s, which “a l l ows one to dialectically ap-p roach the health-disease dyad and the pra c-tices comprising it, leaving room for the re c o g-nition of various planes of emergence, in a com-p l ex system of adaptive pro c e s s e s” (Sa m a j a ,1 9 9 7 : 2 7 2 ) .

In c o r p o rating elements from contempora ryc ritical herm e n e u t i c s, Samaja proposes thatthe object-model “ h e a l t h” should operate un-der four essential ontological determ i n a t i o n s :

No r m a t i ve n e s s. The health object is norm a-t i ve because it exists in and consists of the hi-e ra rchical interfaces in dynamic social and bi-ological systems, both real and ideal, whichshape the human world by means of pro c e s s e si n volving the establishment and evaluation ofn o rms for existence.

D ra m a t i c i s m. The health object is dra m a t i cin two senses: first, in the re c u r s i ve sense, tothe extent that it exists in and consists of itera-t i ve, re p ro d u c t i ve, and tra n s f o rm a t i ve pro c e s s-es of the hiera rchical interfaces; second, dra-matic in a conflictive sense, given that each hi-e ra rchical order maintains a high level of au-tonomy and there f o re of vulnerability vis-à-visthe interf a c e s.

Re f l ex i v i t y. The health object is re f l e x i ve be-cause it exists in and consists of the field of thep rofessed senses and practices experi e n c e dt h rough “p ro d u c t i ve - a p p ro p ri a t i ve (specifical-ly human) conduct”.

Hi s t o r i c i t y. The health object has an onto-socio-genetic nature: it exists in and consists ofthe dialectic of stru c t u ral processes that re c a-pitulate past geneses.

S I

D

N o rmal health(signs & symptons)

Social health (SmpH) Private health (feeling)

Scientific health (concept)

H e a l t h i n e s s Individual health

Philosophical health (value)

DIS Complex and Modes of Health

F i g u re 4

Canguilhem model (adapted).

Page 13: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

GENERAL THEORY OF HEALT H 7 6 5

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

In this pathway of construction, which pur-posely takes health as a social value (and al-most as an ideal type), Samaja highlights itscomplex, plural nature, fundamentally one oflinking multiple determ i n a t i o n s :

The object of Health Sciences, as a complexobject that contains sub-objects with differe n tl e vels of integration (cells, tissues, org a n i s m s ;persons; families; neighborhoods; org a n i z a-tions; cities; nations...), entails a large numberof hiera rchical interfaces and an enorm o u samount of information, in which its experi-ences and postulations (both true and false) onn o rmal/pathological, healthy/ill, and cura-t i ve / p re ve n t i ve acquire meanings and dra m a t-ic dimension (Samaja, 1997).

The author deri ves from these reflections as e ries of epistemological conclusions, amongstwhich he highlights that the theoretical healthfield emerges from the production and form u-lation of what he calls a “p o l i t o m o r p h o u s”k n owledge on the normal-pathological dialec-t i c. To this end, the interd i s c i p l i n a ry field of thehealth sciences is stru c t u red on the cognitivep roduction of the va rious subordinate objects,re vealing different planes of emergence and hi-e ra rchical interf a c e s. The fundamental ques-tion in this epistemological investigation con-sists precisely of the identification of the stru c-t u ring interfaces in the multifaceted totality ofthe object-model “ h e a l t h”. Ac c o rding to Sa m a-ja (1997), the main interfaces of Health are :“molecule//cell (specific category :a u t o p o i e s i s ) ;cell//organism (category : o n t o g e n e s i s ) ; o r g a n-ism//society (category : s t r u c t u ral coupling)”.( Samaja does not refer to an important inter-mediate interf a c e, albeit one that occurs at asubindividual level, involving organs and sys-tems in the organism, and whose specific cate-g o ry might be differentiation. I owe this obser-vation to Lígia Vi e i ra da Si l va, by way of person-al communication.) In addition, he proposes toconsider the interfaces in the societal sphere,playing out as follows: biosociety//gentilic so-c i e t y; gentilic society//political society. Ins h o rt, Sa m a j a’s contribution is a critical pro p o-sition vis-à-vis Ca n g u i l h e m’s thinking, yet onethat intermediates it, allowing for its instru-mentalization as a frame of re f e rence for aGe n e ral T h e o ry of He a l t h .

Tu rning to both the sciences of symbolicsystems and those of org a n i zed biological sys-t e m s, Samaja proposes a perspective whichdoubtless ove rcomes Ka n t’s Problem and up-dates Ca n g u i l h e m’s theory concerning the newp a radigmatic developments in contempora rys c i e n c e. After all, in Ka n t’s time only physics,a s t ro n o m y, and natural history we re consid-

e red science. It is not surprising that for thefounding philosopher of modern epistemolo-g y, it appeared inadmissible to consider a ra d i-cally subjective question (like Health, at leastat the individual level) as a potential pro b l e mfor science. We should not forget that scientificp s ychology and anthropology had still notbeen created, that social re l a t i o n s, the uncon-s c i o u s, and the symbolic contents of cultureand history we re still not scientific objects, andthat the ethnographic method had not beend e veloped. In addition, clinical practice todayis not what it used to be (as for example inyoung Ca n g u i l h e m’s time). Biotechnology hasi n va d e d / t respassed molecules, tissues, org a n s,the human body. Diagnostic classifications, thegenetic code, and the immune system have in-c reasingly become the object of so-called in-f o rmation sciences. A word of caution is thusin order vis-à-vis the radical constru c t i o n i s mp e rmeating any Canguilhem-like analysis,which by appearing to ignore the natura l n e s sof disease, becomes a source of abstract re f l e c-tion which fails to instru m e n t a l i ze a consistentc ritique of the hegemonic medical model.

Modeling health

As discussed above, the biomedical concep-tions of health and the sociocultural theori e sof health-disease present major limitationsthat reduce their value as a conceptual re f e r-ence to deal with the multidimensionality ofthe DIS Complex (disease-illness-sickness).Functionalist medical sociology deve l o p e dp rocessual models for the social determ i n a t i o nof illness that only tangentially allow one to in-fer health as the result of a daily process of con-s t ructing social re s p o n s e s. Neither has medicala n t h ropology ever proposed to define a theo-retical category called “ h e a l t h”, focusing on thee t h n o g raphic specificities of the notion of sick-ness and its corre l a t e s. Despite their theore t i-cal and methodological adva n c e s, both per-s p e c t i ves focus on cura t i ve pra c t i c e s, and inso-far as necessary define health as the absence ofillness or sickness.

The thinking originating from Ca n g u i l h e m’sw o rk effectively constituted an epistemologicalfoundation of the utmost importance for de-veloping new theories of health in the field ofCo l l e c t i ve Health (Caponi, 1997). No n e t h e l e s s,the philosophical approaches to the conceptsof normality and health, by emphasizing theindividual and subindividual levels of analysis,ended up reducing the scope of their contri b u-t i o n s.

Page 14: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

ALMEIDA FILHO, N.7 6 6

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

Despite such limitations and cri t i c i s m s, allthis effort re p resents an inestimable contri b u-tion to theoretical advancement in the healthfield. In the current essay, it was possible tob riefly consider the accumulated heuristic po-tential in the interfaces between the social sci-ences and the health sciences, thus the identi-fication of some objective conditions for thef o rmulation of a proposal to systematize theconceptual problem of He a l t h .

From the pre l i m i n a ry exploration of theepistemological foundations of the health is-s u e, one can re t ri e ve the following potentiallyuseful elements for the current pro p o s a l :

a) In accordance with anthro p o l o g y ’s mul-t i vocal approach in Bibeu and Co ri n’s systemici n t e r p retation of health, the plurality of dis-courses stru c t u red with a scientific basisshould be contemplated in this pro c e s s, shap-ing descriptors capable of ord e ring the possi-bilities for the concept’s empirical re f e re n c e.

b) Co n ve rging with Ca n g u i l h e m’s stance,selected forms of the “ h e a l t h” concept can le-gitimately constitute an ontology of health as ascientific object.

c) Respecting the impasse raised byGa d a m e r, yet re t rieving his argument re g a rd-ing the holistic nature of health, the object-model “ h e a l t h” should incorporate a metasyn-thetic component into its construction, re-specting its integri t y- t o t a l i t y.

d) Co n s i d e ring Sa m a j a’s contribution, ac o n s t ru c t i ve approach to the scientific qualityof “ h e a l t h” should contemplate the field’s hier-a rchical interf a c e s, organizing the concept’se x p l a n a t o ry stru c t u res as a heuristic object-m o d e l .

Based on the investigation into the healthconcept in different contempora ry discourses,I identify the following background issues indi-cating theoretical problems that must be ove r-c o m e :

How to conceptualize health through theplanes of emergence of phenomena and pro c e s s-es that define it concretely? Is it possible to definehealth as a single cross-section, by means of at h e o ry capable of tra n s m i g rating from the indi-vidual-singular to the collective-social leve l s ?

How to absorb the intuitive notion of healthas absence of sickness into a positive conceptof health? And how to link this incorpora t i o ninto the va rious planes of emergence of health-d i s e a s e ?

How to move tow a rds a positive concept ofhealth, considering the concept’s histori c i t yand its applicability as an underlying notion inp rocesses of tra n s f o rmation of a given healths i t u a t i o n ?

Co n s i d e ring the definitions of hiera rc h i c a li n t e rfaces and planes of emergence and inte-g rating the contributions by applied social sci-e n c e s, as re v i e wed above, I propose an effort atsemantic and theoretical specification of whatcould be called Modes of Health, as shown inTable I. This org a n i zes the terminology used forc a t e g o ries of non-health available to the va ri-ous health sciences, in addition to distinguish-ing between the va riations in the definitions ofn o rmality and health and their potential em-p i rical descri p t o r s.

Like any schematic re p resentation, this oneis an attempt at depiction which is necessari l yp a rtial and impove rished in comparison to therich and complex underlying re a l i t y. The va ri-ous modalities of health and the corre s p o n d-ing categories of non-health are org a n i zed ac-c o rding to hiera rchical planes of emerg e n c e :subindividual (systemic//tissual//cellular//molecular), individual (clinical//pri vate), col-l e c t i ve (epidemiological//populational//so-cial). What I propose here is a glossary of cate-g o ries for non-health which in a sense incor-p o rates and expands the pre l i m i n a ry semanticd e m a rcation of disease – illness – sickness.Note that the category “d i s o rd e r” (or t ra n s t o r n oin Po rtuguese) occupies a level equivalent tothe definition of disease in the clinical sphere.

As in any scheme, I seek to indicate equiva-lent descriptors for the re s p e c t i ve level ands p h e re. T h u s, at the subindividual level, nor-mality and pathology (in the original Ca n g u i l-hemian sense) correspond to the descri p t o r“s t a t e”. At the individual level, in the clinicals p h e re, normal health corresponds to disease( s t ru c t u ral) and disorder (functional), having“signs & symptoms” as descri p t o r s.

At the subindividual and individual planesof emerg e n c e, at any level of complexity, thehealth object can be examined based on an ex-p l a n a t o ry approach with a determinant basis,p roducing highly stru c t u red causal metaphors.In this case the issue is to produce (or polish)some partial facets of the object-model He a l t h :the biomolecular process in the normal sys-tems or the sustained physiological process inhealthy subjects as equivalent to the patholog-ical processes as manifested in the “c a s e”, orthe “case of illness”. The constitution of theClinical Medicine disciplinary field around thisfacet of the total health-disease object hasbeen treated both in histori c a l / e p i s t e m o l o g i-cal as well as praxeological terms (Almeida Fi-l h o, 1997; Clavreul, 1978).

Pri vate health, with Ga d a m e rian phenome-n o l o g y, and individual health, the object of an“epidemiology of mode of life”, both refer to the

Page 15: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

GENERAL THEORY OF HEALT H 7 6 7

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

“ i l l n e s s” category, according to the distinctionp roposed under the Su s s e r- K l e i n m a n - Yo u n gline of thought. Note that in each of these casesthe descriptors display a certain sense of an-tagonism: “health status” as the intent to obj e c-tify the individual mode of health and “ h e a l t hf e e l i n g” as the intimate, part i c u l a r, pri va t emode of health, which cannot be made public.

Within this scheme, it is also possible to sit-uate the conventional epidemiological per-s p e c t i ve (the epidemiology of risk factors),founded on an inductive logic with a pro b a-bilistic basis (Almeida Fi l h o, 1997; Ay re s, 1997).From this perspective, the health-disease ob-ject is re p roduced as a specific concept, withrisk production models based on the direct ac-tion or interaction of risk factors. In the epi-demiological sphere of risk analyses, measure-ment-type quantitative descriptors (ra t e s, co-efficients) can deal with the subset’s counter-domain [the sick population groups], equiva-lent to the population residue (1 – ri s k ) .

The notion of public health in the elderCanguilhem, which one can call “ h e a l t h i n e s s” –in contrast with the idea of morbidity in tra d i-tional public health discourse, can have “ h e a l t hs i t u a t i o n” as an efficient descri p t o r. Finally themodes of “social health”, equivalent to the con-cept of sickness in interpre t a t i ve medical an-t h ro p o l o g y, could be approached thro u g hBi b e a u - Co ri n’s systems of signs, meanings, andp ractices of Health (SmpH). Indeed, the Sm p Ht h e o ry provides the possibility of incorpora t i n gsickness into the health concept itself, to theextent that it sees the experience of sickness asa way of stru c t u ring the social re p re s e n t a t i o nof health by constructing subjectivity and thes u b j e c t’s relationship to the material and sym-bolic world.

A synthesis of this initial approach to thep roblem of theoretically defining Health is thatone cannot speak of health in the singular,rather of va rious “ h e a l t h s”, depending on thel e vels of complexity and planes of emerg e n c eat stake. Such an early conclusion is in linewith Cze re s n i a’s (1999) emphasis on the impor-tant difference between pre vention and pro-motion re g a rding the pragmatic use of con-cepts of Health. Howe ve r, this issue is best de-picted in Sol Levine’s insight concerning leve l sof “health re a l i t y ”, as in the following quote:“But what is health? It is, of course, not dire c t l yo b s e rva b l e , but is inferre d . Health is, first of all,a conceptual construct that we develop to en-compass a range of different classes of phenom-ena [... in] three levels of re a l i t y : the physiologi-c a l , the perc e p t u a l , and the behaviora l” (So lL e v i n e, 1995:8).

At this still pre l i m i n a ry stage of explora t i o nand theoretical formulation, there is no doubtthat one must face a new family of objects, i.e. ,object-models not defined by their compo-n e n t s, functional pri n c i p l e s, and dimensions,which do not prove amenable to the pro d u c-tion of knowledge by way of fra g m e n t a t i o n( h e n c e, objects adverse to analytical pro c e s s-es). Such synthetic models tend tow a rds a newd e g ree of formal ascension to become meta-synthetic objects, constructed for (and by) re f-e rence to the facts produced by the so-calledHealth Sciences.

F u rther comments

Be f o re concluding, two questions are in ord e rby way of an ove rall justification for this essay:Why not adopt the health-as-absence-of-dis-

Table 1

Planes of emergence and modes of health.

Planes of Categories Modes of health D e s c r i p t o r se m e rg e n c e of non-health

S u b - i n d i v i d u a l P a t h o l o g y N o rm a l i t y S t a t e

I n d i v i d u a l D i s e a s e N o rmal health Signs & symptoms

D i s o rd e r

I l l n e s s Private health F e e l i n g

Individual health Status

C o l l e c t i v e R i s k (1 – Risk) M e a s u re m e n t

M o r b i d i t y H e a l t h i n e s s S i t u a t i o n

S i c k n e s s Social health SmpH systems

S y n t h e s i s H e a l t h - d i s e a s e - c a re F o rms (integral)

Page 16: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

ALMEIDA FILHO, N.7 6 8

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

ease perspective, as almost eve ryone has done?Why seek to construct a positive health concept?Why propose a Ge n e ral T h e o ry of Health ra t h e rthan a perhaps more realistic unified theory?

The first question has important pra c t i c a land theoretical consequences. Let us first lookat its practical side. In t u i t i ve l y, it is not easy top ropose interventions in a void, aimed at t ra n s-f o rming situations that determine absences,p owe r s, or virt u a l i t i e s. To consolidate subjects’resistance and resilience tow a rds the DIS Co m-plex, to induce an increase in what has beent e rmed social capital (Kawachi, 1999; Ka w a c h iet al., 1999), to re i n f o re the human ties thatp roduce quality of life in daily life through so-cial support networks (Kaplan et al., 1977), ins h o rt, to effectively achieve the much-laudedhealth promotion, we need a specific constru c tto designate Health (Noack, 1987). This meansc o n s t ructing a positive object-model for k n ow l-edge and intervention rather than a negativeobject, a mere conceptual residue from ex-p l a n a t o ry modes of biological and social lifebased on their logical opposite.

The health-as-absence-of-disease perspec-t i ve, albeit conceptually comfortable andmethodologically feasible, cannot fully dealwith the processes and phenomena re f e r ring tol i f e, health, sickness, suffering, and death atany of the levels of reality identified above byLevine (1995). Just as the whole is always g re a t e rthan the sum of its part s, health is much morethan the absence or inverse of sickness. It is ac rucially interesting logical problem, to bes o l ved by ove rcoming the antinomy betwe e nhealth and sickness inherited from the tra d i-tional biomedical model.

Let us re t u rn for a moment to Talcott Pa r-s o n s. In his last work (Pa r s o n s, 1978), a detailedanalysis of the relationship between socialp ractice and the human condition (and a little-k n own and poorly evaluated work, even amongsocial theoreticians), this author resumes thetheme of Health, defining it “as a symbolic cir-culating medium regulating human action andother life pro c e s s e s”, in the context of a curi o u sanalogy with the economic concept of we a l t h(health = wealth). Like curre n c y, Health doesnot constitute a value per se, but does in factbecome a value in exchange pro c e s s e s. T h u s,a c c o rding to Pa r s o n s, Health is not a capacitythat is found in the body, nor even does it re f e rto the individual organism, rather it is a media-tor in the interaction between social subjects.Health is not something that can be “s t o re d”; itonly exists while it circ u l a t e s, when it is “e n-j oye d”. Health, as stated succinctly by Pa r s o n s(1978:69), “is the teleonomic capacity of an in-

dividual living system... the capacity to copewith disturbances... that come either from theinternal operations of the living system itself orf rom interaction with one (or) more of its envi-ro n m e n t s”. Health is thus not the inverse or ab-sence of sickness; and sickness (always i l l n e s s,a c c o rding to Parsons) should be the “o bve r s e”of health.

The second question haunts other contem-p o ra ry scientific fields. The basic difference be-t ween a unified theory and a general theory isthat the former is postulated as a global formof exc l u s i ve and all-encompassing explana-tion, valid for all levels and contexts, while ag e n e ral theory implies altern a t i ve modes of u n-derstanding, respecting the complexity of theobjects and the plurality of different scientifica p p roaches to an interd i s c i p l i n a ry problem.

The epistemological critique expounded inthis paper was highly useful for establishingthe central problem of levels of complexity andplanes of emerg e n c e, indicating that health-disease phenomena cannot be defined as es-sentially an individual-clinical or subindivid-ual-biological issue. In addition, the objects ofHealth are polysemous, plural, multifaceted,t ra n s d i s c i p l i n a ry, simultaneously ontologicaland heuristic models capable of tra ve r s i n g(and being tra versed by) spheres and domainsre f e r ring to different levels of complexity.

I wish to conclude by leaving a hint ofdoubt: and what if Gadamer is right? Pe rh a p shealth is more a question of life than of sci-ence; if so, then it would not make sense toc o n s t ruct it as the object of even re l a t i vely ob-j e c t i ve know l e d g e. It may be that metasynthet-ic and sensitive objects like Health and the DISComplex can only be found beyond proud sci-ence and vain philosophy.

Despite this hint of doubt, it is up to us top roceed. Based on this pre l i m i n a ry essay, wecan test hermeneutic methodologies for inve s-tigating scientific discourses, assuming themno longer as an external object of inquiry, butseeking to re t race the steps of the thematic in-vestigation of health itself and its concern s, are f l e x i ve re s e a rch pro c e s s. The re f l e x i v i t y, sen-s i t i v i t y, and tra n s d i s c i p l i n a rity of the complexobject Health can thus be incorporated intowhat is still a re l a t i vely atypical approach, eve nwithin a paradigm of complexity. In this tenta-t i ve process of constructing a Ge n e ral T h e o ryof Health, it will certainly be necessary to tra n-scend the disciplinary borders between the so-called “n a t u ra l” and human sciences in health.T h u s, perhaps the health sciences, both humanand natural, may actually deserve the title ofLife Sciences.

Page 17: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

GENERAL THEORY OF HEALT H 7 6 9

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

A c k n o w l e d g m e n t s

Study funded by the Brazilian National Re s e a rc hCouncil (CNPq) with Fe l l owship Aw a rd 5 2 0 . 5 7 3 / 9 5 - 1and Grant 463.855/00-0. Ma ria T h e reza Ávila and Fe r-nanda To u rinho Pe res contributed extensively to thel i t e ra t u re re v i e w, Ja i rnilson Paim, Maurício Lima Ba r-re t o, and Lígia Vi e i ra da Si l va collaborated with cri t i-cal reading of the va rious versions of the paper, andDenise Coutinho pro o f read style and word i n g .

R e f e re n c e s

A B E D, L. C., 1993. La Enfermedad en la Hi s t o r i a. Cór-doba: Di rección Ge n e ral de Pu b l i c a c i o n e s, Un i-versidad Nacional de Córdoba.

ALMEIDA FILHO, N., 1997. A Clínica e a Ep i d e m i o l o-g i a. 2a Ed. Rio de Ja n e i ro: APCE/ABRASCO.

ALMEIDA FILHO, N., 2000. What does the word“ h e a l t h” mean? Cadernos de Saúde Pública, 1 6 :3 0 0 - 3 0 1 .

ALMEIDA FILHO, N., in pre s s. O conceito de saúde:Ponto-cego da epidemiologia? Revista Bra s i l e i rade Ep i d e m i o l o g i a.

ALMEIDA FILHO, N.; CORIN, E. & BIBEAU, G., un-published manuscript. Si g n s , Meanings and Pra c-tice in Mental He a l t h : Pa rt II. Methodological Ap-p l i c a t i o n . The Bahia St u d y.

AYRES, J. R., 1997. S o b re o Risco – Pa ra Compre e n d e ra Ep i d e m i o l o g i a. São Paulo: Ed i t o ra Hu c i t e c.

BERLINGUER, G., 1988. A Do e n ç a. São Paulo: Ce n t roBra s i l e i ro de Estudos de Sa ú d e / Ed i t o ra Hu c i t e c.

B I B E AU, G. A., 1988. Step tow a rd thick thinking: Fro mwebs of significance to connections across dim e n-s i o n s. Medical An t h ro p o l o gy Qu a rt e rl y, 2:402-416.

B I B E AU, G., 1994. Hay una enfermedad en las Améri-cas? Ot ro camino de la antropología médica paran u e s t ro tiempo. In: Cu l t u ra y salud en la cons-t rucción de las Améri c a s, VI Co n g reso Co l o m-biano de Antropología, An a l e s, pp. 44-70, Bo g o t á :Instituto Colombiano de Cu l t u ra, Un i versidad delos Andes.

B I B E AU, G. & CORIN, E., 1994. Cu l t u raliser l’ é p i d é m i-ologie psyc h i a t ri q u e. Les systèmes de signes, desens et d’action en santé mentale. In: Ma rc -Ad é l a rd Tremblay ou la construction de l’anthro-pologie québécoise ( P. Charest, F. Trudel & Y. Bre-ton, dir.), Quebec: Presses de l’ Un i versité Lava l .

B I B E AU, G. & CORIN, E., 1995. From submission tothe text to interpre t a t i ve violence. In: Beyond Tex-t u a l i t y. Asceticism and Violence in An t h ro p o l o g i-cal In t e r p re t a t i o n . Ap p roaches to Semiotics Se r i e s(G. Bibeau & E. Co rin, ed.), pp. 3-54, Berlin: Mo u-ton de Gru y t e r.

BOORSE, C., 1975. On the distinction between dis-ease and illness. Philosophy and Public Affairs,5 : 4 9 - 6 8 .

BOORSE, C., 1977. Health as a theoretical concept.Philosophy of Science, 44:542-573.

BOORSE, C., 1997. A rebuttal on health. In: What isDi s e a s e ? (J. Humber & R. Almeder, ed.), pp. 1-134,New Je r s e y: Humana Pre s s.

CANGUILHEM, G., 1966. No u velles Réflexions sur leNormal et le Pa t h o l o g i q u e. Pa ris: P. U . F.

CANGUILHEM, G., 1978. O Normal e o Pa t o l ó g i c o. Riode Ja n e i ro: Fo rense Un i ve r s i t á ri a .

CANGUILHEM, G., 1990. La Santè: Concept Vu l g a i reet Question Ph i l o s o p h i q u e. Toulouse: Sa b l e s.

CAPONI, S., 1997. Ge o rges Canguilhem y el estatutoepistemológico del concepto de salud. Physis –Revista de Saúde Coletiva, 4 : 2 8 7 - 3 0 7 .

C H AVES, M., 1972. Saúde & Si s t e m a s. Rio de Ja n e i ro :Ed i t o ra da Fundação Getúlio Va rg a s.

C LAVREUL, J., 1980. A Ordem Médica. São Paulo: Bra-s i l i e n s e.

C LOUSER, K.; CULVER, C. & GERT, B., 1997. Ma l a d y.In: What is Di s e a s e ? ( J. Humber & R. Almeder,ed.), pp. 175-217, New Je r s e y: Humana Pre s s.

CORIN, E., 1995. The social and cultural matrix ofhealth and disease. In: Why are some Pe o p l eHealthy and others Not? The Determinants ofHealth of Populations (R. G. Eva n s, M. L. Ba rer &R. Ma rm o r, ed.), pp. 93-132, Ha w t h o rn: Aldine deGru y t e r.

CORIN, E.; BIBEAU, G. & UCHÔA, E., 1993. Élémentsd’une sémiologie anthropologique des tro u b l e sp s ychiques chez les Ba m b a ra, Soninké et Bwa duMali. An t h ropologie et Sociétés, 17:125-156.

CORIN, E. & LAU ZON, G., 1992. Po s i t i ve withdra w a land the quest for meaning: The re c o n s t ruction ofe x p e rience among schizo p h re n i c s. Ps y c h i a t ry, 55:2 6 6 - 2 8 1 .

CO S TA, N., 1989. Ensaio sobre os Fundamentos da Ló-g i c a. São Paulo: Ed i t o ra Hu c i t e c / E D U S P.

C U LVER, C. & GERT, B., 1982. Philosophy in Me d i c i n e.O x f o rd: Oxford Un i versity Pre s s.

CZERESNIA, D., 1999. The concept of health and thed i f f e rence between pre vention and pro m o t i o n .Cadernos de Saúde Pública, 15:701-709.

E N G E L H A R D T, T., 1975. The concepts of health andd i s e a s e. In: Evaluation and Explanation in theBiomedical Sciences ( T. En g l e h a rdt & S. F. Sp i c k-e r, ed.), pp. 125-141, Dord recht: D. Reidel Pu b-l i s h i n g .

F I E L D, D., 1976. The social definition of illness. In: AnIn t roduction to Medical Sociology ( D. Tu c k e t t ,ed.), pp. 334-366, London: Ta v i s t o c k .

F O U C AU LT, M., 1963. Naissance de la Clinique: Un eArchéologie du Régard Médical. Pa ris: P. U . F.

F O U C AU LT, M., 1976. Mental Illness & Ps y c h o l o gy.New Yo rk: Harper & Row.

Page 18: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

ALMEIDA FILHO, N.7 7 0

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

F U L F O R D, K. W. M., 1994. Closet logics: Hidden con-ceptual elements in the DSM and ICD classifica-tions of mental disord e r s. In: Philosophical Pe r-s p e c t i ves on Psychiatric Diagnostic Classification( J. Sa d l e r, M. Schartz & O. Wi g g e n s, ed.), pp. 211-232, Ba l t i m o re: Johns Hopkins Un i versity Pre s s.

GADAMER, H. G., 1993. The Enigma of He a l t h. Be rk e-l e y: St a n f o rd Un i versity Pre s s.

G O N Ç A LVES, R. B. M., 1992. Práticas de Saúde: Pro-cesso de Trabalho e Necessidades. Cadernos CEF O R– Textos 1. São Paulo: Ce n t ro de Fo rmação dosTra b a l h a d o res da Sa ú d e.

G O O D, B., 1994. Me d i c i n e ,R a t i o n a l i t y, and Ex p e r i-e n c e . An An t h ropological Pe r s p e c t i ve. New Yo rk :Ca m b ridge Un i versity Pre s s.

G O O D, B. & GOOD, M. J., 1980. The meaning of symp-toms: A cultural hermeneutic model for clinicalp ra c t i c e. In: The Re l e vance of Social Science forMedicine (L. Ei s e n b e rg & A. Kleinman, ed.), pp.165-196, Dord recht: D. Reidel Pu b l i s h i n g .

G O O D, B. & GOOD, M. J., 1982. Tow a rd a meaning-c e n t e red analysis of popular illness categori e s :‘Fright Il l n e s s’ and ‘He a rt Di s t re s s’ in Iran. In :Cu l t u ral Conceptions of Mental Health and Ther-apy (A. J. Marsella & G. M. W h i t e, ed.), pp. 141-166, Dord recht: D. Reidel Pu b l i s h i n g .

HELLER, A., 1986. La Teoria de las Necessidades enMa r x. Ba rcelona: Pe n í n s u l a .

H E S S LOW, G., 1993. Do we need a concept of disease?T h e o retical Me d i c i n e, 14:1-14.

HUMBER, J. & ALMEDER, R. (ed.), 1997. What is Di s-ease? New Je r s e y: Humana Pre s s.

I N E COM, 1993. The International Ne t w o rk for Cu l t u r-al Ep i d e m i o l o gy and Community Mental He a l t h.Mo n t real: World Health Organization Co l l a b o ra t-ing Ce n t re for Re s e a rch and Training in Me n t a lHe a l t h .

K A P LAN, B.; CASSEL, J. & GORE, S., 1977. Social sup-p o rt and health. Medical Ca re, 15:47-58.

K AWACHI, I., 1999. Social capital and community ef-fects on population and individual health. An n a l sof the New Yo rk Academy of Sciences, 896:120-130.

K AWACHI, I.; KENNEDY, B. P. & GLASS, R., 1999. So-cial capital and self-rated health: A contextuala n a l y s i s. American Journal of Public He a l t h ,8 9 : 1 1 8 7 - 1 1 9 3 .

KLEINMAN, A., 1980. Patients and Healers in the Con-t ext of Cu l t u re. Be rk e l e y: Un i versity of Ca l i f o rn i aPre s s.

KLEINMAN, A., 1986. Concepts and a model for thec o m p a rison of medical systems as cultural sys-t e m s. In: Concepts of He a l t h , Illness and Di s e a s e .A Compara t i ve Pe r s p e c t i ve (C. Cu r rer & M. St a c e y,ed.), pp. 29-47, Oxford: Be rg Pu b l i s h e r s.

KLEINMAN, A., 1988. The Illness Na r ra t i ve s : Su f f e r-i n g , Healing & The Human Condition. New Yo rk :Basic Bo o k s.

KLEINMAN, A., 1992. Local worlds of suffering: An in-terpersonal focus for ethnographies of illness ex-p e ri e n c e. Qu a l i t a t i ve Health Re s e a rc h, 2:127-134.

KLEINMAN, A.; E I N S E N B E RG, L. & GOOD, B., 1978.Cu l t u re, illness, and care. Clinical lessons fro ma n t h ropologic and cro s s - c u l t u ral re s e a rch. An-nals of Internal Me d i c i n e, 88:251-258.

LAKOFF, G., 1993. Women, Fire,and Dangerous T h i n g s.Be rk e l e y: Un i versity of Ca l i f o rnia Pre s s.

L EVINE, S., 1995. The meanings of health, illness andquality of life. In: Quality of Life and He a l t h .C o n-c e p t s , Me t h o d s , and Ap p l i c a t i o n s (I. Gu g g e n m o o s -Holzmann, K. Bloomfield, H. Brenner & U. Fl i c k ,ed.), pp. 7-14, Berlin: Bl a c k well Wi s s e n s c h a f t s -Ve r l a g .

MASSÉ, R., 1995. Cu l t u re et Santé Pu b l i q u e. Mo n t re a l :Gaetan Mo ri n .

M U R PH Y, E., 1965. The Logic of Me d i c i n e. Ba l t i m o re :Johns Hopkins Un i versity Pre s s.

N OACK, H., 1987. Concepts of health and health pro-motion. In: Me a s u rement in Health Pro m o t i o nand Protection (T. Abelin, Z. Brzezinski & V.Ca r s t a i r s, ed.), WHO Regional Pu b l i c a t i o n s, Eu ro-pean Se ries 22, pp. 5-28, Copenhagen: Wo r l dHealth Org a n i z a t i o n .

N O R D E N F E L D, L., 1987. On the Na t u re of He a l t h.D o rd recht: D. Reidel Pu b l i s h i n g .

N O R D E N F E L D, L., 1993. Quality of Li f e , Health andHa p p i n e s s. Aldershot: Ave b u ry.

OXFORD DICTIONARY, 1968. O x f o rd English Di c t i o-n a ry. New Yo rk: Oxford Un i versity Pre s s.

PAIM, J., 1996. A situação de saúde no Brasil e osmodelos assistenciais. In: IV En c o n t ro Especialda Sociedade Bra s i l e i ra para o Pro g resso da Ciên-cia (SBPC), An a i s, pp. 249-253. Fe i ra de Sa n t a n a :S B P C .

PARSONS, T., 1951. The Social Sy s t e m. New Yo rk: Fre ePre s s.

PARSONS, T., 1964. Social St r u c t u re and Pe r s o n a l i t y.New Yo rk: Free Pre s s.

PARSONS, T., 1975. The sick role and the role of thephysician re c o n s i d e red. M M F Q / Health Sociology,5 3 : 2 5 7 - 2 7 8 .

PARSONS, T., 1978. Action Theory and Human Condi-t i o n. New Yo rk: Free Pre s s.

PE R E Z - TA M AYO, R., 1988. El Concepto de En f e r m e-d a d. México, DF: Fondo de Cu l t u ra Ec o n ó m i c a .

PÖRN, I., 1984. An equilibrium model of health. In :He a l t h , Di s e a s e , and Causal Explanations in Me d-icine (L. No rdenfeld & J. Odelstad, ed.), pp. 225-238, Dord recht: D. Reidel Pu b l i s h i n g .

PÖRN, I., 1993. Health and adaptedness. T h e o re t i c a lMe d i c i n e , 1 4 : 2 9 5 - 3 0 3 .

SAMAJA, J., 1994. Epistemología y Me t o d o l o g í a. Bu e-nos Aires: EUDEBA.

SAMAJA, J., 1997. Fundamentos Epistemológicos delas Ciencias de la Salud. Doctoral T h e s i s, Rio deJa n e i ro: Escola Nacional de Saúde Pública/Fu n-dação Oswaldo Cru z .

SUSSER, M., 1973. Causal Thinking in the Health Sci-e n c e s. New Yo rk: Oxford Un i versity Pre s s.

TEMKIN, O., 1963. The scientific approach to disease:Specific entity and individual sickness. In: S c i e n-tific Change: Historical Studies in the In t e l l e c t u a l ,S o c i a l , and Technical Conditions for ScientificDi s c ove ry (A. Cro m b i e, ed.), pp. 629-647, Ne wYo rk: Basic Bo o k s.

YOUNG, A., 1980. The discourse on stress and the re-p roduction of conventional know l e d g e. S o c i a lScience and Me d i c i n e, 1 4 8 : 1 3 3 - 1 4 6 .

YOUNG, A., 1982. The anthropologies of illness ands i c k n e s s. Annual Re v i ews of An t h ro p o l o gy, 1 1 : 2 5 7 -2 8 5 .

Page 19: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

GENERAL THEORY OF HEALT H 7 7 1

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

Ro b e rto Br i c e ñ o - L e ó n

Health and the lack there o f

In his interesting art i c l e, Naomar Almeida Fi-lho complains that sociology has failed to pro-vide an answer to the search for a general theo-ry of health, but does a general theory of healthreally make sense?

Health is a polysemous notion. Its multiplemeanings are hidden or disguised under thecloak of the idea that when it is missing, specif-ic facts like diseases are expressed, but thatwhen it is present, it displays more desires andillusions than realities capable of embodying ag e n e ral theory.

Health is like one of those signifiers that theu n c o n s c i o u s, in the Lacanian view (Lacan,1966), employs to add successive and mutablem e a n i n g s. And this is what happens when oneattempts to state – reasonably too much so –that health is not only “the absence of disease”,and one postulates “maximum we l l - b e i n g” as ap o s i t i ve definition. Maximum well-being is asignifier full of multiple meanings, since it em-bodies a fleeting desire, a fantasy quite appro-p riate to the contempora ry quest for happi-n e s s, which can take the form of fre e - o f - e ve ry-thing (salt, sugar, etc.) diets, body worshipt h rough exercise training, the re s u rgence ofnew and old re l i g i o n s, and the narcissism of ro-mantic love. Still, is health happiness?

It is interesting that Almeida Filho has toappeal to disease to define health, when suche rudite and we l l - a rgued positions from Ha r-va rd, with A. Kleinman, and Mo n t real, Bi b e a u -Co rin, also refer systematically to disease.Whether the concept is disease, illness, or sick-n e s s, the issue is infirmity of the body, the con-s c i o u s, or social re l a t i o n s. One does not speakof health, but of infirm i t y. Health is what is losts o m e w h e re and is defined more by its hollow-ness than its content.

Disease defines health, just as death de-fines life. As written by Wittgenstein (1973), it isnot that death leads us to silence, since deathis not part of life. Death, perhaps rather as con-c e i ved by Heidegger (1962), gives tra n s c e n-dence to life; the awareness of death gives im-pulse to transcendent actions and to the con-cept of health as this goal of delaying death byextending life expectancy, or that pushes away

Debate on the paper by Naomar de Almeida Filho

Debate sobre o artigo de Naomar de Almeida Filho

La b o ratório de Ciencias S o c i a l e s , Un i versidad Ce n t ral de Ve n e z u e l a ,Ca ra c a s , Ve n e z u e l a .

its tra i t s, like disabilities, which are announcedd u ring life.

Both disease and illness are always socialc o n s t ru c t s, whether deri ved from witchcraft orscientific know l e d g e, but which are also a partof a cultural context that mediates them andg i ves them meaning and forc e. Or that give sthem legitimacy to link to other social re l at i o n s,to justify absence from work or claim re i m-bursement from one’s insurance company. Ye tthey are also silences that speak, telling of whatis ye a rned for but not named.

Yet health is all the more a construct in thatit is located in the shifting terrain of desire. It isa construct of the way of understanding theb o d y, its vigor and we a k n e s s, its odors ands t e n c h e s, its presence and finitude. But it is ac o n s t ruct where social goals always play a ro l e,defined as historically and socially possible, aswell as the individual desires forged in theimagination. The individual scale of health ex-p resses the ideal self (i d e a l i c h) that has beenf o rged in the social context and that prov i d e sthe support to be expressed in beauty, longevi-t y, enjoyment, or quality of life as the exerc i s eof potentialities, in the sense proposed by Se n(1973). Health is another way of expressing in-dividual and social aspirations in a histori c a lmoment, but in a ve ry dramatic dimension,since it is part of our social narcissism, whichtends to shun re a l i t y, always fleeing tow a rd sthe imaginary. That is why health, at the imagi-n a ry level, can take the form of individual eco-nomic success, social re volution, or nirva n a .

Health as a general theory does not exist.T h e re are only historical claims, demarc a t i n gwhat we are missing. Gadamer is right when heconsiders health elliptic. Almeida Filho stalksit, queries it, but doubts. Ne ve rtheless this isthe ra zo r’s edge on which one must move for-w a rd. Health is our desire for completeness,our narcissism, our endless quest to fill the gapthat makes us mort a l s. T h e re are thre a t s, therea re pro m i s e s, there are changes, there are loss-e s. But eve rything that is reached is ephemera l ,e ve rything is imaginary and at the same timereal. Thus any presumption of a general or lifesciences theory should labor to grasp this m ove-ment, this permanent and unattainable tre n dthat longs to be health when it longs to besomething more than the simple absence of in-f i rm i t y. Thus health should have as an essentialcomponent the acceptance of what is missing,the incompleteness and imperfection that wea re, since the best of all healths will never saveus from infirmity and death. And death mustbe an essential component of any life science,because it gives meaning to the mutant tempo-

Page 20: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

ALMEIDA FILHO, N.7 7 2

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

rality that we are. Because this is the time ofour being, and thus the poet port rays us: “Yo u r sis the time through which your body passes/withthe trembling of the world,/time,not your b o d y. . . /Yours is the touch of hands, not the hands;/thelight filling your eyes, not the eyes;/perhaps at re e , a bird you watch,/the rest is beyond./We on-ly bear the time of being alive/between the light-ning and the wind;/the time in which your bodyspins with the worl d , / t o d a y, the cry of the mira-cle;/the flame that burns with the candle, n o tthe candle...” ( Mo n t e j o, 1996:162).

HEIDEGGER, M., 1962. Ser y Ti e m p o. Ma d rid: Jo s éGa o s.

LACAN, J., 1966. É c r i t s . Pa ris: Éditions du Se u i l .M O N T E J O, E., 1996. An t o l o g í a. Ca racas: Mo n t e a v i l a

Ed i t o re s.SEN, A., 1993. Capability and well-being. In: The Qu a l-

ity of Li f e (K. Nusbauun & A. Sen, ed.), pp. 30-54,O x f o rd: Oxford Un i versity Pre s s.

W I TTGENSTEIN, L., 1973. Tractatus Logico-Ph i l o-s o p h i c u s . Ma d rid: Ti e rno Ga l va n .

De p a rtamento deFi l o s o f i a , Facultad de Filosofia y Hu m a n i d a d e s ,Un i versidad de Chile,Santiago de Chile, C h i l e .

Miguel Ko t t ow Public health and individual morbidity

It may be pertinent to speak of a health-diseasedyad, but such pairing has its pri c e. A dyad ism o re than just two of a kind; it implies a cer-tain categorical opposition where one term ex-cludes the other – either healthy or not healthy.The opposite of health is non-health (or “u n-h e a l t h”), which may be disease, illness, sick-n e s s, or malady, so there is no real dyad unlesswe create one: health-morbidity. W h e reas dis-e a s e, illness, and sickness form a family of con-cepts in need of definitions, the Ge rm a nKra n k h e i or its Spanish equivalent e n f e r m e d a da re polysemous and open to hermeneutic in-t e r p re t a t i o n s. The differences are cultural, andt ranslations only stress and distort the actualuse of language. Too much emphasis is put on[ a r b i t ra ry] definitions; what matters are the ac-tions that such concepts denote and elicit.

T h e re seems to be fair agreement that dis-ease is a medical description of organismic dis-o rd e r s, subject to hard description and quan-tification aimed at achieving causal explana-tions and specific interve n t i o n s, whereas ill-ness is the experience of abnormality in formor function. Di s o rder and deviation necessari l yrefer to some standard of normalcy which may

be described for the species (Boorse), althoughit seems more to the point that the individualconstitutes his own standard of health/mor-bidity (K. Goldstein). Ne ve rt h e l e s s, it is ra re l ya c k n owledged that feeling ill may lead to twod i f f e rent attitudes: unexplained, intolera b l e,and uncontrollable suffering that leads one toseek therapeutic assistance; or physical dis-c o m f o rt that is predictably tempora ry and ex-pected to go away spontaneously. The differ-ence is between suffering hematuria and hav-ing the flu, between having an illness and feel-ing sick. This important distinction needs aname and in fact has one in daily parlance: aperson feels sick after eating spoiled seafood, orsuffers from sea-sickness, or a pregnant womanfeels morning sickness but knows she is not ill.All such cases of sickness will probably not leadthe individual to seek medical advice. While ill-ness leads one to seek medical help, sickness re-mains in the realm of bearable unpleasantness.

The habitual experience of sickness dis-owns Tw a d d l e’s suggestion that it is a social la-bel assigned to individuals incapable of per-f o rming their roles in a normal way. If philoso-phy is not to interf e re with the actual use oflanguage (Wittgenstein), then sickness is a t e rmthat must pre s e rve its eve ryday use, thus deny-ing that society participates in defining mor-b i d i t y. Ra t h e r, social forces analyze medical la-beling of disease and decide upon pert i n e n ts t rategies for insura n c e, medical care, subs i d i a ryfinancing, and re s o u rce allocation. Me d i c i n ed e s c ribes organismic disord e r s, while societye valuates them. In order to adequately fulfilltheir functions, public policies must find a fitb e t ween the scientific view of disease and thes u b j e c t i ve experience of uncontrollable illness.

It is true that illness, medical definition ofd i s e a s e, therapeutic effort s, and social supporta re all culturally influenced, and social envi-ronments certainly play a central pathogenicrole in many disord e r s. Ne ve rt h e l e s s, it is theindividual who experiences illness, and it is inthe unique physician-patient encounter wheredisease is detected, labeled, and subject to ap-p ro p riate treatment. All these experiences areof course value-laden, and it is a mistake to aimat va l u e - f ree definitions in the health/morbidi-ty complex. Bioethics has stressed that medicale xcellence depends on taking due notice of thes u b j e c t i ve illness component. The clinical en-c o u n t e r, where illness is presented and diseaseis re c o g n i zed, is a strictly medical situation, al-though strongly influenced by many extra -medical factors.

W h e re does this perhaps exc e s s i vely de-tailed analysis leave the concept of health? Is it

Page 21: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

GENERAL THEORY OF HEALT H 7 7 3

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

not, after all, the default state of any org a n i s mwhich has no [detectable] morbidity – Bi c h a t’ssilence of the organs? Health is not an experi-e n c e, nor is it a recognizable state of the org a n-ism, for medicine can probe and certify then o rmalcy of certain functions, but never ex-h a u s t i vely of the organism as a whole. Me d i c a le f f o rts aim at eliminating disease, or pre ve n t-ing it when a person is vulnerable: its task endswhen disease is re m oved (Gadamer). If healthcould be described and medicine we re to bec h a rged with protecting it, we would be open-ing the doors to an incommensurable and un-d e s i rable medicalization of human life, far be-yond what already occurs. All the more so if weg i ve in to the temptation of creating totalhealth-disease objects with hiera rchical leve l s,for then health and disease become an endlessl a b o ra t o ry exploration in the sub-individualre a l m .

If health remains a negative idea, it ceasesto sustain health care pro g rams and publichealth policies, which appear to become con-ceptually void and fall into pragmatic steri l i t y.Does this also make public health a non-enti-ty? Ce rtainly not. Morbidity in all its forms is astate of individual org a n i s m s. Public healthcannot be a state, it rather must be seen as ane n v i ronmental process concerned with cre a t-ing social and ecological conditions of suchquality as to help citizens ave rt morbidity andbecome less vulnerable to external nox a e. Mo rethan a positive concept of individual health, weneed to act upon socially induced pathogenicfactors and create living conditions that allowsingle organisms to live in biologically and an-t h ropologically friendly enviro n m e n t s, fre ef rom the risks of social and ecological tox i c i t y.We might gain some distinctness and clarity ofconcepts if we spoke of public health as a so-cial strategy to reduce the risks of individualmorbidity – disease, illness, and sickness ac-c o rding to agreed-upon definitions. Pu b l i chealth acts at the collective level to control fac-tors that cause disease and influence the or-g a n i s m’s well-being from o u t s i d e the individ-ual, whereas medicine is less concerned withhealth than with treating derangements thatoccur w i t h i n the individual. If more efficientpublic health policies lead to less individualm o r b i d i t y, we will have there by discove red at rue and useful dyadic re l a t i o n s h i p.

De p a rtmento de Epidemiologia e Métodos Qu a n t i t a t i vo sem Saúde, Escola Nacional de SaúdeP ú b l i c a , Fundação Oswaldo Cruz,Rio de Ja n e i ro, Bra s i l .

Luis Da v i dCa s t i e l

To be necessarily pre c i s e . . .or precisely necessary ?

“We end up shaping the world as if it allowed it-self to be re d u c e d , h e re and there , to intelligiblee l e m e n t s . Sometimes our senses are sufficientfor this purpose, and other times more inge-nious methods are employ e d , but empty spacesa re left. The attempts remain full of gaps (...)”( Paul Va l é ry, 1998).

Once again, Naomar de Almeida Filho hasp roduced an essay in which his undeniable tal-ent as scholarly b r i c o l e u r e m e rges clearly, withhis skillfully fertile innovation in the field ofphilosophical reflection on health. For thosewho are unaccustomed to treading on such a ri dg round, it is a landscape which can give onethe impression of dangerously approaching in-nocuousness and/or irre l e vance in the face ofthe instrumental pre s s u res increasingly char-a c t e rizing the health domain. Yet in this casethe author has constructed a vigorous and s t i m-ulating conceptual and epistemological fra m e-w o rk, under the pre l i m i n a ry format of what herefers to as a “Ge n e ral T h e o ry of He a l t h”, wiselyexplaining beforehand the caution re q u i red forsuch a daunting task.

The synthesis is extremely helpful in the p re-sentation to the socio-anthropological (func-tionalist, phenomenological, semeiologic) andepistemological approaches as a prior re v i e wto the proposed systematization of ‘modes ofh e a l t h’ that concludes the essay.

My modest attempt to contribute to the de-bate is based on two points which tend to jux-tapose: (a) the question as to whether “ h e a l t h[can] be treated as a scientific concept” and (b)the “hint of doubt” mentioned by the Ba h i a nepidemiologist as to the possibility of Ga d a m e rbeing right. In other word s, it becomes com-pelling that health is something individual, pri-va t e, unique, and subjective [indeed, in myv i e w, not a ve ry simple conclusion, contra ry towhat Almeida Filho contends, since if the con-clusion we re simple it would not entail the se-rious implication of making the ‘s c i e n t i f i c i z a-t i o n’ of the object health pro b l e m a t i c ] .

On this point, I believe that it is appro p ri a t eto consider the uncomfortable possibility of afleeting and simultaneous “c o e x i s t e n c e” of as-pects that are defined/undefined, pre c i s e / i m-p re c i s e, accessible/inaccessible, unknown – p o-tentially cognoscible/unknowable – i n c o g n o s c i-b l e, in the demarcation of what health finallyi s. As Moles (1995:45) puts it, “the human spiritis fluid in its functioning, ambiguous in its con-

Page 22: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

ALMEIDA FILHO, N.7 7 4

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

c e p t s , and vague in its definitions”. Ac c o rd i n gto the latter author, one of the categories of thei m p recise relates to “phenomena that are va g u ein essence (author’s emphasis), or in which theconcepts used to enunciate them are themselve sva g u e , p e rhaps inadequate, but which are theonly ones we have ava i l a b l e” (Mo l e s, 1995:19).In short, the words of Moles (or Va l é ry ’s epi-g raph) appro p riately re p resent my impre s s i o n swhile reading Almeida Fi l h o’s pro p o s i t i o n s.

Mo re specifically, I wish to highlight seve ra lissues for discussion on this stimulating art i-c l e :

The pre l i m i n a ry establishment of a “s e-mantic demarc a t i o n”, or correspondence be-tween the terms used in English and Port u g u e s e(disease = p a t o l o g i a, disord e r = t ra n s t o r n o,e t c.) is not without side effects. We know thatw o rds have the stubborn “p ro p e rty” of un-masking themselves in the face of our attemptsto circ u m s c ribe them in stabilized meanings.Vi s i b l y, as in Fi g u re 1, to use p a t o l o g i a to meanboth “pathology” and “d i s e a s e” may lead tom i s u n d e r s t a n d i n g s. I do not believe that to re-fer re s p e c t i vely to the “Canguilhemian (i.e. ,sub-individual) sense” or to the “s t ru c t u ral (in-dividual) re g i s t e r” satisfactorily re s o l ves thisfocus of potential equivo c a t i o n .

I believe that as a scholar of etymology(note his timely editorial in Cadernos de SaúdeP ú b l i c a on the etymology of “ h e a l t h”), AlmeidaFilho should consider that one cannot heed-lessly conduct a semantic demarcation ofd o e n ç a as the equivalent of “s i c k n e s s”, re l a t i n gto the collective realm. Do e n ç a [as disease] isc o n s e c rated not only by common sense, but bythe biomedical litera t u re. The Po rt u g u e s e - l a n-guage term d o e n ç a o riginally comes from theLatin d o l e n t i a , which in turn comes from d o l-e re, to hurt [or to gri e ve, as in the English do-lent – T. N.]. In this case, Ga d a m e r’s arg u m e n tis imperi o u s, since pain is normally re f e r red toat the individual level as being personal and in-a l i e n a b l e, with a high level of “s u b j e c t i v i t y ”.

The article was not intended to analyze ine x t e n s i ve detail the conditions for possible de-m a rcation of “modes of health” or the re s p e c-t i ve “d e s c ri p t o r s”. Even so, at first glance, somespecific aspects appear to demand greater clar-ification and elaboration. An example is themode of health re f e r red to as “1 – ri s k”, some-thing which, by the way, appears to be concep-tually f r i s k y [a play on words by the discussantusing r i s c o, or risk, and a r i s c o, i.e., frisky orundisciplined – T. N.]... If epidemiological ri s k sa re measured and indicated by way of numeri-cal va l u e s, what is the cut-off point whichclearly defines which groups are actually at ri s k

and which are not? How does one deal with them o re elderly age bra c k e t s, increasingly pre s e n tin the Brazilian population py ra m i d s, whererisks appear to pro l i f e rate with the expansionof vulnerabilities arising from aging?

It is appro p riate to recall here that the dis-cussions on risk extend beyond the stri c t l yq u a n t i t a t i ve epidemiological appro a c h e s. T h enotion of “ri s k” is, pardon the term, pro t e i f o rm ,i . e., it can invo l ve va rious aspects: economic( u n e m p l oyment, pove rty), environmental (va r-ious types of pollution), re l a t i ve to personalconduct (“impro p e r” ways of eating and dri n k-ing, not exercising), interpersonal (ways of es-tablishing and maintaining amorous and sexu-al relations), and “c ri m i n a l” (events linked tourban violence) (Lupton, 1999). All of these“ri s k s” “f e rm e n t”, mixing and ove rf l owing intothe cultural realm, becoming signs and symbols.

In short, the “e x p e ri e n c e” of risk plays ani n c reasingly active role in the shaping of iden-tity matrices and in the formation of subjectiv-i t i e s, prone to interpre t a t i o n s, amenable to ap-p roaches by SmpH. In this sense, SmpH de-s c riptors are linked not only to the non-healthc a t e g o ry “s i c k n e s s”, but also to “ri s k” as “s o c i a lp e rc e p t i o n”. What name should be used for thisc a t e g o ry? (danger, threat? – and in Po rt u g u e s e ?a m e a ç a, p e r i g o?) Is it appro p riate to baptize it?How does one deal with the antagonism be-t ween the “health feeling” – an aspect that as-sumes an “intimate, particular, private [ m o d e ] . . .which cannot be made public” and “health sta-t u s”, which seeks to “objectify the individualmode of health”?. Fu rt h e rm o re, how can onerefer to something as a “d e s c ri p t o r” when it isc o n s i d e red indescri b a b l e, i.e., that which “c a n-not be made public”? Pe rh a p s, at best, it mayonly be “d e s c ri b a b l e” in litera ry or poetict e rm s, but this is not the realm of the curre n td i s c u s s i o n .

Two further observations may be superf l u-o u s, especially since they relate to incidentalcomments in the essay:

St rictly speaking “L a k o f f ’s pro t o t y p e s” arenot “L a k o f f ’s”... In fact, this theory of catego-rization originates from the so-called “t h e o ryof basic level prototypes and categori e s” con-c e i ved by Eleanor Rosch and colleagues, as in-dicated by Lakoff himself (1987) in the studycited by Almeida Fi l h o. Since the theory wasp resented ve ry succinctly, clearly in keepingwith the purpose of Almeida Fi l h o’s art i c l e, Iwill take this priceless opportunity to present adetailed description, given the re l e vance ofthese ideas (see Castiel, 1999).

As Almeida Filho states so well, there arec i rcumstances in which no pro p e rt y, attri b u t e,

Page 23: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

GENERAL THEORY OF HEALT H 7 7 5

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

or chara c t e ristic is sufficient or necessary todefine (in accordance with formal categori c a llogic) the case as belonging to the category.T h e re are other modes of categorizing, basedon cri t e ria of familiar similari t y, centra l i t y, andp ro t o t y p i c a l i t y. These modes are anterior tothe acquisition of logical-formal thinking. Su c hideas we re developed and systematized by thelinguist Eleanor Rosch (1978) and colleagues ina general theory, based on empirical studiesthat challenged the classical point of view ofc a t e g o ri z a t i o n .

Ac c o rding to the formal/classical theory, nomember of a category holds any primacy ove ro t h e r s, since the aspects that define elementsbelonging to a given category are shared by allthe members. Rosch (1978) showed in studieson the categories of color in the Dani languagein New Guinea, which has two basic categori e sof color (m i l i – for dark, cold shades and m o l a– for light, hot shades) that there is an inclina-tion or trend by individuals to choose given ex-amples of the mola c o l o r s. In other word s, theya re considered prototypical – more re p re s e n t a-t i ve than the others. In other word s, there area s y m m e t ries (prototypical effects) betwe e nmembers of the category and asymmetri c a ls t ru c t u res within the categori e s. Another ex-ample: in relation to the “ b i rd” category, stud-ies have shown that individuals indicate ca-n a ries and chickens as more re p re s e n t a t i ve ofthe category than penguins and ostri c h e s.

It is important to emphasize that the cate-g o rical stru c t u re plays an essential role in thep rocesses of reasoning and constitution ofc o n c e p t s. Under many circ u m s t a n c e s, pro t o-types act as va rious types of cognitive points ofre f e rence and form the basis for infere n c e s.

T h e re also occur what are called “basic lev-el effects” (Rosch, 1978). That is, there are lev-els that are more intelligible and prone to con-ceptualization than others. For example: basicl e vel categories tend to be perc e i ved better –“s n a k e” is grasped better than the hiera rc h i c a l-ly superior level “re p t i l e” or the subord i n a t el e vel “pit viper” or “boa constri c t o r”.

Fe r re i ra (1996) conducted an inve s t i g a t i o nthat attempted to determine whether the theo-ry of prototypes and centrality could be ve ri-fied in samples within the Brazilian context.His results corro b o rate the consistency of thew o rk by Eleanor Ro s c h’s gro u p.

T h e re is evidence that the categories wee rect are hetero g e n e o u s, beginning with theirc o g n i t i ve ori g i n s. Human capacities to deter-mine them are relational and also depend onour history of re c i p rocal effects with the world,that is, they simultaneously invo l ve an inter-

acting multiplicity of biological, cultural, andsocial elements. Ca t e g o rizing skills appearm o re objective and accurate when re f e r red tothe basic leve l .

In short, categories depend on the ways inwhich individuals act with objects – how theyp e rc e i ve, construct images, org a n i ze inform a-tion, and behave in relation to them. Basic lev-el categories thus possess different pro p e rt i e sf rom the others. They are amenable to chara c-t e rization by means of images or motor ac-t i o n s. For example, the concept of “c h a i r” iseasier to conceive than that of “f u rn i t u re”(Lakoff, 1987).

It is important to highlight that fuzzy logicas originally developed by Lotfi Zadeh does notexactly consist of an a l t e r n a t i ve logic that goesb e yond the categorical logic that presides stan-d a rd set theory. In broad term s, Zadeh (1965)c o n c e i ved an ingenious perfection of standardset theory to model categories that allow forg radation – even describable by continuous“va ri a b l e s”. In a classic set we have dichoto-mous aspects (either one is inside the catego-ry – 1; or outside it – 0); in a fuzzy set, as de-fined by Zadeh, it is possible to consider inter-mediate values between 0 and 1. T h u s, theRosch prototype theory does not appear to meto be amenable to immediate understandingby such logic, as Almeida Filho suggests.

The most recent edition of the standardBrazilian dictionary Aurélio (1999) presents thedefinition for “o bve r s e” in the realm of logic assomething resulting from obversion, that is, “avalid immediate inference for any type of cate-g o rical proposition obtained by changing thequality of the proposition and replacing thep redicate with its complement. Thus all S is P,by obversion, will be no S is non-P”. We canthus “push the arg u m e n t” and obversely com-mit the following “d e d u c t i o n”: if all health isthe absence of disease, no health is thus thep resence of disease?! One clearly perc e i ves theweakness and impro p riety of this pro p o s i t i o n .This proposition of the reductio ad absurd u mtype illustrates an improper exercise in form a llogical reasoning in the field of health and life,which should be used with extreme caution,since the results may be fallacious.

In a word, the purpose of this commentarywas to emphasize that along with the pro g re s-sion in attempts to provide intelligibility to ourobjects of study, we should consider the possi-bility that there may be unattainable dimen-sions in this rationalist thrust that are pro p e rto contempora ry We s t e rn thought. For exam-p l e, what is the “p re c i s i o n” that can be re a c h e dby linking “planes of emerg e n c e”, “c a t e g o ries of

Page 24: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

ALMEIDA FILHO, N.7 7 6

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

n o n - h e a l t h”, “modes of health”, and “d e s c ri p-t o r s” within these laby rinthine domains thatmay perchance be health (whether in the sin-g u l a r, or in the plural, as “ h e a l t h s”). If it is nec-e s s a ry (insofar as possible...) to make our ob-jects of study more precise in order for the ra-tionalist device to work, how should we pro-ceed when we fail to achieve any clarity or pre-cision in distinguishing all these items?

Fu rt h e rm o re, how do we know, in our questto demarcate objects, when we produce notobject-models but create object-artifacts andreify and fetishize them? It is hard to say, I ad-mit. Yet even agreeing partially with AlmeidaFilho that “it is up to us to pro c e e d”, it appearsto me to be appro p riate to question, gently andc a re f u l l y, how much good it actually does us int e rms of advancement in health know l e d g eand practices to pursue our impetus forw a rd . . .I believe there are moments in which oneshould take a brief “puzzled pause” to attemptto get some idea of the effects/results of our ir-re p ressible dri ve to know and produce objects.On such occasions, even with some re s i s t a n c e,it is important to consider being penetra t e d( s l ow and easy, mind you) beyond a hint ofd o u b t . . .

CASTIEL, L. D., 1999. A Medida do Po s s í ve l . S a ú d e ,R i s c o, Te c n o b i o c i ê n c i a s. Rio de Ja n e i ro: Ed i t o raFi o c ru z / Ed i t o ra Co n t ra c a p a .

FERREIRA, A. B. H., 1999. Novo Aurélio Século XXI: ODicionário da Língua Po rt u g u e s a. Rio de Ja n e i ro :Nova Fro n t e i ra .

FERREIRA, M. C., 1996. Estru t u ra interna de catego-rias semânticas e seus efeitos no pro c e s s a m e n t oc o g n i t i vo. In: Psicologia e Mente Social. C o n s-trução de Teorias e Problemas Me t o d o l ó g i c o s (S. L.C. Fe rnandes & M. Ca s t a n h e i ra, org.), pp. 127-143, Rio de Ja n e i ro: Ed i t o ria Ce n t ral da Un i ve r s i-dade Gama Fi l h o.

LAKOFF, G., 1987. Women, Fire,and Dangerous T h i n g s .What Categories Re veal about the Mi n d. Chicago:Un i versity of Chicago Pre s s.

LU P TON, D., 1999. R i s k. New Yo rk: Ro u t l e d g e.MOLES, A. A., 1995. As Ciências do Im p re c i s o. Rio de

Ja n e i ro: Civilização Bra s i l e i ra .ROSCH, E. & LLOY D, B. B., 1978. Cognition and Ca t e-

g o r i z a t i o n . Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum Associ-a t e s.

VA L É RY, P., 1998. In t rodução ao Método de Leonard oda Vi n c i. Rio de Ja n e i ro. Ed i t o ra 34.

ZADEH, L., 1965. Fuzzy sets. Information and C o n t ro l,8 : 3 3 8 - 3 5 3 .

Pre s i d ê n c i a , Fu n d a ç ã oOswaldo Cruz,Rio de Ja n e i ro, Bra s i l .

Maria Cecília deSouza Mi n a y o

Health as a scientific object and a theme for life

Almeia Fi l h o’s essay For a Ge n e ral Theory ofHe a l t h : Pre l i m i n a ry Epistemological and An-t h ropological Notes is surprising because of thel e vel of intellectual energy with which the au-thor launches into such a complex and diffi-cult-to-define terrain, especially because hep roposes to enter into the merit of defining at h e o ry. Yet to construct a theory means firstand foremost to believe that it is possible to ex-plain or comprehend a phenomenon and thep rocesses by which it is re a l i zed. It is this majoru n d e rtaking that Almeida Filho embra c e s, sur-mounting the first difficulty by seeking to dif-f e rentiate what might be called a Unified Theo-ry f rom a Ge n e ral Theory.

Despite the inestimable value of the au-t h o r’s contribution for those who construct thet h e o retical practice of health, I see his work asan initial or p re l i m i n a ry a p p roach, as he him-self states it. T h i s, because to construct a theo-ry corresponds to the design of an org a n i ze dsystem of p ropositions that are logical con-s t ructs and guide data acquisition and analy-s i s, like the elaboration of c o n c e p t s that arec o g n i t i ve, pragmatic, and communicational ar-tifacts bearing the theory ’s meaning. Be yo n dt h i s, the idea of constructing a theory by con-s t ructing an org a n i zed whole has genera l l ybeen applied more to the universe of disci-plines and to the elaboration of schools ofthought. To date, health has never been tre a t e das either a discipline or school of thought, butrather as a field of knowledge and pra c t i c e s,within which there is a quest for scientific au-t h o ri t y, technical capacity, and social powe r( Bo u rdieu, 1975); or as a living labora t o ry in-volving persons, equipment, experi e n c e s, ro l e s,and stra t e g i e s. (Latour & Wo o l g a r, 1979). In thiss e n s e, I consider it quite problematic to form u-late a theory of health or health models. It is ad i f f e rent matter to theori ze the health concept,which is ultimately the art i c l e’s attempt.

At any ra t e, the paper corresponds to thediscussion and to the enunciation of a possiblet h e o ry, which leads us to ask whether the au-thor intends to reflect on the health theme as ad i f f e rentiated discipline. It behooves AlmeidaFilho to provide us with another act of his cre-a t i ve energ y, tackling the challenges of delvingdeeply into the constitution of this g e n e ral the-o ry. This is crucial, since as one utilizes a set oflogically related pro p o s i t i o n s, such a theorymust provide an ord e r, a system, an org a n i z a-

Page 25: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

GENERAL THEORY OF HEALT H 7 7 7

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

tional fra m e w o rk for thought, and its art i c u l a-tion with concrete re a l i t y, in an attempt to beunderstood by a community which follows thesame path of reflection and action.

The concept-making undertaking is highlyi m p o rtant and meri t o ri o u s. The author pre-sents a vast bibliographical re v i e w, ra n g i n gf rom seminal texts to contempora ry studies,which he uses to re l a t i v i ze, challenge, or re a f-f i rm the classics. And by blazing this intellectu-al trail, Almeida Filho helps shed light on theobject at hand, besides raising questions andhypotheses with great pro p riety and tracing as p i ral path to the conclusion, which was thebeginning of his queri e s, relativizing his ow ni d e a s. I confess that I am curious to see the se-quel to the scientific construction of theory,since it differs from the limited line of what hasbeen conceived to date in sciences (includingthe social sciences) concerning g e n e ral theory.

I would like to raise seve ral questions basedon these initial observa t i o n s. The first is thatf rom the ve ry beginning of the paper, in myopinion, Almeida Filho falls into a theore t i c a lt rap when he identifies as stru c t u ring dimen-sions of the scientific field of health “the socio-a n t h ropological dimension and the epistemo-logical dimension”. I ask: is the epistemologicaldimension stru c t u ring or is it part of the meta-analysis of theories? On the other hand, whenhe says that “despite recognizing its import a n c eand founding ro l e , the biological dimensionwill not be cove red here , except insofar as itp roves indispensable to clarify some specific is-sue in the health-disease models analyzed here-i n”, is the author not losing a basic stru c t u ri n gdimension of the biological/social hybrid?

This is so true that the entire paper is per-meated by the discourse on the biological, onphenomena and processes of falling ill, eve nwhen they appear in the widely va rying seman-tic connotations presented by the author. W h a tI am saying is that it becomes impossible tot h e o ri ze about health/disease without dealingsimultaneously with aspects of the biological/social hybrid. The exclusion of one elementf rom the dyad jeopard i zes the discussion.

T h e re is one further problematic point inthe path chosen by Almeida Fi l h o, namely thefact that the texts on which the author baseshis essay are the results of a long-standing,f i rmly based, and sophisticated reflection bythe so-called Anglo-Sa xon (especially No rt hA m e rican) school of medical anthropology ands o c i o l o g y. The fact is that since their birt h ,these disciplines are firmly linked to know l-edge of diseases, to the point that the term“ h e a l t h” follows in the wake of such know l e d g e

and is thus launched into a reductionist sem a n-tic spectrum whose center is the attempt toa void risk and maintain a vision of norm a l i t y.Almeida Fi l h o’s paper itself, intended as a pre-l i m i n a ry thrust tow a rds a t h e o ry of health, failsto escape this theoretical entanglement, leav-ing until the end a slightly more open discus-sion (albeit still not systematized) based on theideas of Canguilhem, Ricardo Bu e n o, and Sa-maja, together with some rather succinct ob-s e rvations on Kant and Ga d a m e r, the latter em-phasizing health at the individual leve l .

I do not know if I can contri b u t e, but basedon my theoretical reflections I will highlighttwo points. One pertains to the differe n t i a t i o nb e t ween the notion of health as a total socialf a c t ( Ma u s s, 1974) and the notion of health as aconcept dealt with by a specific sector, consti-tuting itself as a field of theoretical and healthc a re practices and policies.

In the former case, h e a l t h constitutes thec o re of human experience in society in its es-sential expression, since it means the synthesisof well-being, individual and social quality ofl i f e, cultural forms of pre s e rvation of existenceand the species, and above all, collective effort sand disputes by differentiated social groups toestablish parameters for what it means to b eh e a l t h y. Obv i o u s l y, as Almeida Filho re c a l l s,within any society this m a t e r-notion is con-s t ructed (by its intellectuals and institutions)t h rough the interpretation and re i n t e r p re t ationof the socio-political and existential p ro c e s s e sof the entire society, through intera c t i ve dy-n a m i c s. Lévy- St rauss (1967), studying pri m i t i vec o m m u n i t i e s, noted that the well-being andpain we feel are socially constructed. In thiss e n s e, health is a good: social and collective; itis a social and political conquest; it is an ex-p ression: cultural and moral. This great Gi f t ,which the poor confuse with wealth and therich go to great lengths to make eternal, eve ndefines a society’s level of development anddenotes the entire inter-play of its intern a lf o rces to achieve what are considered ideal pa-ra m e t e r s.

Indeed, to conceive of health from thispoint of view allows one to glimpse it as an ob-ject of knowledge linking biology both to an-t h ropology and to specific policies or econom-i c s. In this world of life, health is not confusedwith the opposite of diseases, because the per-son can have specific problems affecting his orher body or mind and consider himself or her-self healthy. Disease can mean a privileged mo-ment in life to achieve new healthy forms ofg rowth and transcendence of personal limita-t i o n s. In this re g a rd it is important to quote

Page 26: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

ALMEIDA FILHO, N.7 7 8

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

Ol i ver Sa c k s, this amazing neurologist who de-voted his life to exploring the world of the so-called “a b n o rm a l”, who in the fore w o rd to hisbook, An An t h ropologist on Ma r s, states that “Iam led to believe that it would be necessary toredefine the concepts of health/disease to viewthem in terms of the body’s capacity to create an ew organization and a new ord e r, adequate forits special disposition and modified accord i n gto its needs, rather than referred to a rigid ‘n o r m’”( Sa c k s, 1995:18). Stated differe n t l y, health can-not be confused with complete well-being asp roposed according to the classical definitionby the World Health Organization or with nor-mality or absence of disease, terms that gove rnmedical logic. Di s o rders and diseases mayh a ve the para d oxical magic of re vealing latentp owe r s, displaying a cre a t i ve we l l s p ring, bothindividual and collective. While they can de-s t roy pathways, they can also re veal new form sof transcendence unimagined in their absence.Hence the study of health is a topic delving in-to the complexity of organization of life and vi-tal pro c e s s e s.

With re g a rd to the concept of health asdealt with in health care and the theore t i c a lp ractice of health, we fail to escape from thechalk circle of the biomedical paradigm, inwhich medical anthro p o l o g y, collective health,and the entire medical system are enmeshed.

Thus Almeida Fi l h o’s paper merits gre a tp raise as part of an effort by numerous authorsto unshackle the concept of health from thei m b ro g l i o of pre vailing medical ideology. T h i se f f o rt is all the more crucial because the ra p i dd e velopment of biology, the adoption of newlife styles, and the quest for environmental ad-equacy increasingly demand that the role ofhealth (which is much broader and more com-plex than that of medicine) be differe n t i a t e df rom the biomedical model. He n c e, even whenbased on the epidemiological morbidity/mor-tality pro f i l e, health proposals will be in har-mony with that broad notion that society de-fines as its essential level of healthy existenceand its development threshold. In addition,h e a l t h’s role must be based on new theories ofcomplexity that deal with the notion of a cer-tain level of instability and imbalance – and notthat of normality – as essential for a healthyl i f e. It is imbalance and imperfection that allowthe effort and increased capacity to tra n s c e n dp revious thresholds in both individual and col-l e c t i ve life. To be healthy (or “to have health” )will always be less to possess a state of norm a l-ity and more to experience dynamics in exis-tence that shift between disorder and ord e r,f rom suffering to pleasure, from the capacity to

maintain an identity to the quest for unexpect-ed growth and evo l u t i o n .

I am certain that by proposing to intro d u c ea t h e o ry of health, Almeida Filho intends to en-c o u rage us to rethink the paradigms that areour birt h p l a c e. T h u s, his essay is an invitationto redefine such para d i g m s, seeking an en-hanced approach to the phenomenon/pro c e s sthat touches us so closely in our essential lifeand death dra m a s.

BOURDIEU, P., 1975. O campo científico. In: P i e r reBo u rd i e u : Sociologia (R. Ortiz, org.), pp. 37-52,São Pa u l o. Ed i t o ra Ática.

LATOUR, B. & WO O LGAN, S. 1979. La b o ra t o ry Li f e .The Oral Construction of Scientific Fa c t s. Be ve r l yHills: Sage Pu b l i c a t i o n s.

L É V Y- S T R AUSS, C., 1967. An t ropologia Es t r u t u ra l.Rio de Ja n e i ro: Ed i t o ra Tempo Bra s i l e i ro.

M AUSS, M., 1974. Sociologia e An t ro p o l o g i a. v. I. S ã oPaulo: EPU/EDUSP.

S ACKS, O. , 1 9 9 5 . Um An t ropólogo em Ma rt e. SãoPa u l o. Companhia das Letra s.

De p a rtamento de Epidemiologia e Métodos Qu a n t i t a t i vo sem Saúde, Escola Nacional de SaúdeP ú b l i c a , Fundação Oswaldo Cruz,Rio de Ja n e i ro, Bra s i l .

Dina Cze re s n i a When I re c e i ved this article by Naomar deAlmeida Filho for comment, I recalled his pa-per entitled Cu r rent Problems and Pe r s p e c t i ve sin Epidemiological Re s e a rch in Social Me d i c i n e,which provided the basis for the book Ep i d e m i-ologia sem Número s ( Epidemiology Wi t h o u tNumbers). Written in the 1980s, the book was amajor stimulus for reflection on epidemiologi-cal know l e d g e. I now perc e i ve the same dari n gand generous chara c t e ristic of open-minded-n e s s, debating even with himself, instigating,full of questions that incite us to think.

The art i c l e’s goal is to conduct a pre l i m i-n a ry evaluation of conditions allowing for aGe n e ral T h e o ry of Health, seeking to achievethe scientific construction of the object “ h e a l t h”t h rough models of health and disease. The au-thors asks: Is a Ge n e ral T h e o ry of Health feasi-ble? Can health be treated as a scientific ob-ject? Does this undertaking invo l ve an underly-ing philosophical problem or some essentialepistemological obstacle? Is health a pro b l e mfor science or a question that relates to life?

Such queries are now emerging acutely inthe field of Co l l e c t i ve Health, insofar as the no-tion of health promotion is increasingly identi-fied as a perspective for intervention. Tra d i-tional Public Health models are based on an e g a t i ve object, namely disease. How does one

Page 27: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

GENERAL THEORY OF HEALT H 7 7 9

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

attain the inverse of this object? How does onec o n s t ruct positive models for knowledge andi n t e rvention in health without a specific theo-retical construct defining health?

No scientific definition of health has beenfound to date. Understood as positivity, healthhas a meaning as broad as the ve ry notion oflife itself. When we refer to terms such as we l l -being and quality of life, linked to the idea ofp romoting health, we are in fact dealing withontological questions like pleasure, virt u e, andh a p p i n e s s. No matter how concise and tra n s-d i s c i p l i n a ry the attempt may be, there is noway of translating such life experiences into ascientific concept. From this existential per-s p e c t i ve, health can only be defined as enunci-ated by Canguilhem (1990): “a commonplaceconcept or a philosophical question”.

Howe ve r, it is certain that the possibility ofa philosophical health does not pre vent onef rom taking health as a scientific object. On c eagain Canguilhem states (1990:35): “The re c o g-nition of health as the truth of bodies in the on-tological sense not only can but should admitthe presence – as a margin and barrier, p ro p e rl yspeaking – of truth in its logical sense, that is,s c i e n c e . The living body is certainly not an ob-j e c t , but for man, to live is also to know”.

The health field has stru c t u red itself histor-ically as linked to medicine, but from the pointof view of Co l l e c t i ve Health, the constru c t i o nof truth in the logical sense is not limited tom e d i c i n e. Co l l e c t i ve Health is a prime spacefor opening to, and interface with, other are a sthat legitimately produce knowledge on health.Howe ve r, no matter how integrated and bro a dthis knowledge is, it does not fail to be a con-s t ruction of truth in the logical sense, pre s e n t-ing itself “as a margin and a barri e r” vis-à-visthe purpose of promoting the health of popu-l a t i o n s. What are the possibilities and limits of afield of knowledge and practices in dealing withan “o b j e c t” that has an ontological meaning?

The complexity of the relationship betwe e nk n owledge and existence is at the root of thedifficulty in elaborating a positive concept ofhealth. T h e re is no theory capable of re s o l v i n gthe tension between life defined as subjectivee x p e rience and that which is the object of sci-e n c e s. Life Science defines health by its in-ve r s e, but without the inexo rability of pain ands u f f e ring would a field of health make sense? Isthe problem the fact that we do not work withp o s i t i ve concepts of health, or is it the implica-tion of constituting a concept of disease inm o d e rn i t y, or even the form in which this con-cept is org a n i zed in practices that either favo ror jeopard i ze life?

In this sense, the issue is not to solve the in-completeness of such knowledge but pre c i s e l yto know how to accept it. I do not mean to dis-qualify such know l e d g e, but to qualify it in thesense of re i n f o rcing the need to reflect on howto link health knowledge to the perspective ofbeing truly useful for health promotion, that is,p romotion of life. This invo l ves affirming a com-p l e m e n t a ry approach in action between mutu-ally different languages, restating the impor-tance of the role of philosophy, art, and politics.

In the solving concrete pro b l e m s, know i n gh ow to re l a t i v i ze the importance of know l e d g ewithout overlooking it is not a simple issue andis not a task for a specific field. Recognition ofthis limit implies a world view tra n s f o rm a t i o nwhich would certainly be translated specifical-ly into profound changes in the logic of tra i n-ing human re s o u rces and formulating and op-e rationalizing health pra c t i c e s.

The effort to construct scientific know l e d g eon health from a synthetic perspective is highlyp e rtinent, seeking to integrate the multiple andcomplex dimensions of this object. But thist ra n s d i s c i p l i n a ry stance, as the author states, isorganized around problems and not discip l i n e s,demanding altern a t i ve and plural modes ofunderstanding. From this broad view, would itnot be contra d i c t o ry to conceive a Ge n e ral T h e-o ry of Health? T h i s, because it would not beone theory, but as many theories as there we rea l t e rn a t i ve and plural modes of appro a c h i n gthis object.

CANGUILHEM, G., 1990. La Santé: Concept Vu l g a i re eQuestion Ph i l o s o p h i q u e. Pa ris: Sa b l e s.

De p a rtamento de En s i n o, Instituto Fernandes Fi g u e i ra ,Fundação Oswaldo Cruz,Rio de Ja n e i ro, Bra s i l .

Suely De s l a n d e s Almeida Fi l h o’s essay is stimulating, as indeedis all of his work. Mo re than as a text, let us ap-p roach it, as proposed by Anatol Ro s e n f e l d(1985), as a “p re - t e x t”, a pretext for dialogue,h a p p e n i n g s, and creation. The “t e x t” will bethis construction in movement, this totality ofa rg u m e n t s, intensities, and intention. So let ustackle the debate.

By proposing a discussion on the pre re q u i-sites for formulating a General Theory of He a l t h ,Almeida Filho constructs a chain of arg u m e n tconcluding that available readings on thehealth object/field/concept are incapable oft ranscending the negative view of “health as

Page 28: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

ALMEIDA FILHO, N.7 8 0

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

absence of disease” and are hence unfit to con-s t ruct a “T h e o ry of He a l t h”. Na t u ra l l y, this epis-temological arc h i t e c t u re is not new, in fact it isa common pathway for those who attempt toove rcome a hegemonic paradigm or para d i g-matic re f e re n c e s, i.e., to seek to demonstra t ethat the explanatory power of certain theori e shas grown stale and that it is urgent to sur-mount them. This demands a profound cri-tique “f rom the inside”, i.e., demarcating thelimitations of that theory or discipline’s toolsbased on its own logic. Un f o rt u n a t e l y, in thiscase sociology was taken for one of its schools,that of functionalism, and its authors we re“e va l u a t e d” based on the operational conceptsthey use, considered “re ve a l i n g” of their adher-ence to the negative view of health. The art i c l eloses sight of the theoretical context of eachauthor quoted in the pro c e s s, the many otherreadings from the domain of “sociology ofh e a l t h” itself, and the analysis of sociologistsi n c o r p o rated into the Co l l e c t i ve Health debate(like Ha b e rm a s, Bo u rdieu, and Gi d d e n s, to citejust those best known to the general public)which have certainly expanded the health con-cept and health praxis well beyond the equa-tion “health = non-disease”.

Ac c o rding to the author, anthro p o l o g y, ase x p ressed by the watershed of medical anthro-p o l o g y, has advanced in the effort at conceptu-alizing the DIS complex (disease, illness, sick-ness), but has failed to ove rcome the essentialp roblem of pri o ritizing the ill individual’s re-t u rn to functioning with a normal and healthyl i f e, without entering into the issue of what thisn o rmality is or the concept of health impliedt h e rein. Again, the rich dimension is often re-duced to examining the basic concepts, andwhen the author re c o g n i zes in certain authors( Young and Bi b e a u - Co rin, for example) a ten-dency to re t ri e ve historical totality, a link be-t ween “the micro and the macro”, a synergy be-t ween individual action and histori c a l / c u l t u ra ls t ru c t u re s, he appears to find a new undert a k-ing which in fact has been a daily issue for dis-cussion in the Social Sciences for at least twe n-ty ye a r s. Since so-called “ra d i c a l” phenomenol-ogy had great influence on the field of health inthe 1970s and now re t u rns in adulterated fash-ion under the veil of methodological impre c i-s i o n s, empiricist spontaneity, and studies erro-neously re f e r red to as “q u a l i t a t i ve re s e a rc h”,one can understand the author’s concern .

The “inability” to ove rcome the negative vi-sion of health still pre va i l s. Howe ve r, perhaps itis not a matter of viewing health as “the mereabsence of disease-illness-sickness”, hence ana b s e n c e in terms of what health is in fact. Bu t

would the issue not be to re c o g n i ze that thehuman experience of health has adhered to(not only dialectically but “ontologically”) theve ry clash, the ve ry struggle against death andthe fear of pain, suffering, and destruction? No tas non-disease but as the unceasing stru g g l eboth against maculae (s a n u s) and at the samet i m e for physical, psychological, and cultura li n t e g rity (s a l v u s) (Almeida Fi l h o, 2000), mean-w h i l e, always noting the historicity of this con-f rontation, since as mentioned above the his-t o ricity of the object is the reality principle ofSocial Sciences (Pa s s e ron, 1995). Once re-m oved from this dimension, does the conceptof health not become watered down? This doesnot indicate ignoring the need, identified sowell by Almeida Fi l h o’s paper, to undertake areflection that ove rcomes the view of health asthe mere inverse of disease.

In fact not only sociology but also the socialsciences (and the so-called natural sciences aswell) are i n s u f f i c i e n t for an understanding/ex-planation of what health is, this polysemousand complex field/object. Still, as postulated,we run the risk of basing the discussion of thisinsufficiency (which is rich because it makesdialogue with other fields of knowledge indis-pensable) on an argument of i n c a p a c i t y, basedon a rapid and external review of what thesesciences are.

But the debate does not end here. It ra i s e sthe bothersome question: is it possible to con-s t ruct a Ge n e ral T h e o ry of Health? And wewould add to this: is it possible and desira b l etoday to construct a Ge n e ral T h e o ry? Many au-thors in Mo d e rnity have followed this enticingp roposition, albeit in the form of a “u n i f i e dt h e o ry ”. At any ra t e, therein lies the idea of at h e o retical construct, hence a w a y - o f - s e e i n g,capable of ex p l a i n i n g the concatenation/func-t i o n i n g / o rganization of a set of phenomena orof the social order itself. The so-called “t o t a lt h e o ri e s” that circulated in the 19th centuryand surv i ved the 20th century articulated dis-c i p l i n a ry knowledge and even provided a num-ber of multidisciplinary pro p o s i t i o n s. T h e ymade an effort to tra n s l a t e, measure, and pre-dict the complex, the future, and even the in-c o m m e n s u ra b l e. They achieved historical suc-c e s s, although orthopedically framing the re a lin re a l i t y; after all, they had at hand some cer-tainties and the notion that the gaps in know l-edge had already been identified.

Still, the paper’s objective is precisely todistinguish itself from this mold: it does notp ropose a total theory, but altern a t i ve modesof understanding, respecting the complexity ofthe objects (hence there is not one health ob-

Page 29: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

GENERAL THEORY OF HEALT H 7 8 1

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

ject, but va rious objects, shaped by the re s p e c-t i ve disciplinary perspectives) and the plura l i t yof this scientific task with a problem which isby definition interd i s c i p l i n a ry.

The author courageously proposes to tackleother powe rful obstacles that resist attempts ata Ge n e ral T h e o ry. The basic dimension of anyt h e o ry, the concept, re veals the challenge ofp re s e rving its totality and polysemy, mean-while being “o b j e c t i f y i n g”. It becomes neces-s a ry to discern in the word h e a l t h what is de-fined as concept, object, object-model, andfield, both with re g a rd to the heuristic aspectand the socio-cultural practices imbedded inthese definitions (which are not re s t ricted toSmpH but connect to a sociology of know l-e d g e ) .

Some doubts remain as to the intents andtheir mode of pre s e n t a t i o n / o rganization. AGe n e ral T h e o ry is proposed in which each fieldof knowledge plays a ro l e, contributing withc e rtain opera t o r s. Ad h e red to each other with-in this theoretical system, which is understoodas open, would such distinct epistemic tra d i-tions be comfortable? Would the “d e s c ri p t o r s”be the possibility of o b j e c t i v i t y capable ofequalizing or assuaging such radical differ-ences as well as promoting a trans- or interd i s-c i p l i n a ry dialogue? Na t u rally any theory must“semantically discipline” the words and con-cepts it employs (Pa s s e ron, 1995). But howdoes one avoid tra n s f o rming such a pro p o s i-tion into the grammar of a formal system? Howdoes one resist succumbing to the clutches ofs t ru c t u ralist logic? Thinking out loud, how d o e sone pre s e rve the p o i e s i s, so dear to the com-plex thinking we claim for the health field, ifone implicitly determines disciplinary roles ap r i o r i?

Gi ven the limited space for debate, I wish toconclude by saying how happy I am to be ableto initiate a dense debate, made possible bysuch a challenging text by Almeida Fi l h o.

Ac k n ow l e d g m e n t s

My thanks to Ed u a rdo Alves Mendonça with whom Ihad the good fortune of discussing this re v i e w.

ALMEIDA FILHO, N., 2000. Qual o sentido do term osaúde? Cadernos de Saúde Pública, 16:300-301.

PA S S E RON, J. C., 1995. O Raciocínio Sociológico. O Es-paço Não-Popperiano do Raciocínio Na t u ra l. Pe-trópolis: Voze s.

RO S E N F E L D, A., 1985. Tex t o / C o n t ex t o. São Pa u l o :Pe r s p e c t i va

De p a rtamento de Medicina Social,Faculdade de Ci ê n c i a sM é d i c a s , Santa Casa de São Pa u l o,São Pa u l o, Bra s i l .

Rita Ba r ra d a sBa ra t a

In For a Ge n e ral Theory of He a l t h : Pre l i m i n a ryEpistemological and An t h ro p o l o g i c a l No t e s,Naomar Almeida Filho proposes an entire re-s e a rch pro g ram that could result in the form u-lation of a Ge n e ral T h e o ry of He a l t h .

Almeida Fi l h o’s article provides a careful re-view of production concerning the conceptsand analytical categories proposed by differe n tauthors for an understanding of the health-dis-ease pro c e s s e s, critically highlighting the limi-tation of models that have focused pri m a ri l yon disease rather than health. Faced with thisre i t e ra t i ve observation concerning the contri-butions of medical sociology, anthro p o l o g y,and epistemology, we must ask the reason forsuch a sharp detour? W h e re precisely lies theimpossibility of conceiving of health? One hy-p o t h e s i s, based on the contributions of Ca n-guilhem and Agnes He l l e r, suggests searc h i n gthe theories of needs for a possible explana-tion. Di s e a s e, as a concrete need objectified byi n d i v i d u a l s, necessarily appears as the objectof reflection and action. Canguilhem calls at-tention to the existential fact that the sufferi n gd e ri ved from diseases historically precedes thet h e o retical elaboration of diseases, thus givingp recedence to what is experienced or “ l i ve d” asc o m p a red to what is reflected upon. Me a n-w h i l e, health is a utopia, a radical need in thesense used by Agnes He l l e r. In pra c t i c e, the l i m-its of capitalist social organization made healthneeds impossible (and thus radical) for signifi-cant portions of the population. To what extentmight this utopian nature of health have func-tioned as an epistemological obstacle to thef o rmulation of a positive theory ?

Re t u rning to the beginning of the art i c l e,t h e re are seve ral re m a rks to be made to help ex-pand the re s e a rch pro g ram proposed there i n .

Beginning with the contributions of med-ical sociology, I consider two aspects funda-mental. The author emphasizes the pre d o m i-nantly biological re f e rence in the appro a c h e she analyze s. Still, more than the biological as-p e c t s, what appears to be at stake is the exc l u-s i vely functionalist approach present in all thec o n t ributions and the fact that the analyses arelimited to the individual, the hypothetical sub-ject of the diseases, illnesses, sicknesses, etc.None of these contributions succeeds in con-ceiving of disease as a social and histori c a lphenomenon with a collective dimension. Inaddition, the abstract systemic conception pre-vents the identification of different hiera rc h i-cal levels among the phenomena. Hence theemphasis on the biological per se does not ex-

Page 30: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

ALMEIDA FILHO, N.7 8 2

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

plain the insufficiency of these appro a c h e s, al-though it has certainly contributed in the sensethat the “negation of the biological” has ap-p e a red as an altern a t i ve for the construction ofm o re appro p riate theories in the anthro p o l o g i-cal watershed.

Fu rt h e rm o re, the author limits himself toanalyzing functionalist contributions fro mmedical sociology. The absence of re p re s e n t a-t i ves of other currents of thought like Si e g e ri s t ,Pollack, and Juan Cesar Ga rcia further accentsthe critical analysis presented by the author, inthe sense of the theoretical pri o rity ascribed tod i s e a s e, to the detriment of health. I do notmean to suggest that such authors have solve dthe problem presented here, but their contri-butions could be as useful to the undert a k i n gas those of the functionalist sociologists. Su c hrecourse to their work could allow for the in-c o r p o ration of elements from medical sociolo-gy into the more promising contributions ofboth medical anthropology and epistemology.

In this sense the analytical scheme ofBibeau and Co rin appears as a truly social for-mulation among those analyzed by the author,re c ove ring the historical, social, and collectivedimensions of the health-disease pro c e s s, al-though it continues to concede greater re l e-vance to the disease pole. Ne ve rt h e l e s s, itwould be worthwhile to ask whether this deve l-opment is sufficient to consider it an adequated e s c riptor for the category of social health pro-posed by the author. Is the attempt at “c l o s i n g”the fra m e w o rk not too hasty, given the pre c a ri-ous state of the re f l e c t i o n s ?

The contributions contained in Juan Sa m a-j a’s cre a t i ve reflection allow one to glimpse thepossibility of ove rcoming many of the antino-mies that have marked the health field. T h et h e o ry of adaptive complex systems doubtlessf u rnishes a matrix to conceive of links betwe e nthe biological/natura l / h i s t o rical/social; tom o re consistently elaborate the relations of de-t e rmination and mediation between the differ-ent hiera rchical levels in the constitution of re-a l i t y; to ove rcome the subjectivization/objec-tivization dichotomy.

The scheme proposed by Almeida Filho inFi g u re 1 can serve as a map to begin the marc hin this re s e a rch pro g ram, but along the ro a dt h e re will most certainly be a series of detoursand sidesteps that will not make the path easi-e r, but which may lead us to discover a morebeautiful landscape.

Instituto de Me d i c i n aS o c i a l , Un i versidade doEstado do Rio de Ja n e i ro,Rio de Ja n e i ro, Bra s i l .

Madel T. Lu z My first comment is how current, re l e vant, andb road is the theme discussed by the author: theabsence of a Ge n e ral T h e o ry of Health in thisi n t e rd i s c i p l i n a ry field of scientific pro d u c t i o nand intervention which until recently wascalled Social Medicine or Public Health, andwhich we now quite significantly refer to asCo l l e c t i ve Health. One should also emphasize,at least in the conceptual terms in which theauthor situates his analysis, how unique hist reatment of the topic is, as far as I know, espe-cially in its original area, that of Ep i d e m i o l o g y.

The second comment is that the theore t i c a l“vacuity” re f e r ring to a positivity of health isp resent as demonstrated by Almeida Fi l h o, notonly in Ep i d e m i o l o g y, the object of a pre v i o u ss t u d y, complementary to this art i c l e, but alsoin the ve ry field of human sciences focusing onthe health-disease process in society and cul-t u re. Utilizing the basic categories present inthis field (disease-illness-sickness) and re l a t e do n e s, conducting what he terms a semeiologica n a l y s i s, the author develops an extensive, in-t e n s e, and erudite discussion with the mainA n g l o - A m e rican schools of thought in the f i e l d sof medical sociology and anthro p o l o g y, subse-quently delving into the main lines of contem-p o ra ry epistemology.

As a third comment, I wish to emphasizethat this conceptual and theoretical “vo i d” islinked pri m a rily to the predominance of thebiomedical frame of re f e rence in the social sci-ences (as the author demonstrates) vis-à-visphenomena related to discomfort, sufferi n g ,and the loss of health and life by individuals,g ro u p s, and communities. What pre d o m i n a t e sin this frame of re f e rence are categories thatobjectify pathology, disease, infirm i t y, as we l las pairs of opposites such as norm a l i t y / a b n o r-m a l i t y, ability/disability, etc.

But the predominance of such categories isalso presented (and here I begin my fourt hcomment) in culture and in basic social re l a-tions as a whole in contempora ry society, be-coming, for the subject, a storehouse of mean-ings in relation to the aforementioned phe-nomena.

He n c e, the “objectivity” of such phenome-na also becomes “subjectivity”: the va ri o u ssubjects come to perc e i ve and feel the loss (orthe pre s e rvation) of their vitality “ by the b o o k s”,i . e., as established in norm a t i ve terms by soci-ety and its institutions. The establishment ofmeanings in the scientific disciplines, whetherf rom the biomedical or social field, is not dis-connected from the historical development of

Page 31: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

GENERAL THEORY OF HEALT H 7 8 3

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

m o d e rn society (quite to the contra ry), fro mthe establishment of institutionally “va l i d”meanings for the subject.

Parsonian functionalist sociological t h o u g h twas unsurpassed in perceiving and giving formto this imbrication between vital ord e r and i n-stitutional ord e r in modern societies. It was nocoincidence that the key category in Pa r s o n’sthinking was that of social ord e r, allied with thec e n t ral concept of social system. Howe ve r, thisi m b rication has affected social thought sincethe 19th century and is at the central constitu-t i ve thrust of the human sciences, as highlight-ed by Foucault in his Les Mots et les Choses, andcan be flagrant in certain aspects of the work ofDu rkheim, of whom Parsons is a professed dis-c i p l e.

The issue of social order (and hence that ofdeviation) identified with the polarity of socialn o rm a l i t y / d i s o rder (or disturbance), and thelatter indirectly with the life/death polarity is akey point in the identification of sickness/dis-ease with vital disord e r and of the latter withthe indirect identification with the polarity o r-d e r / n o r m a l i t y, and d i s o rd e r / d e v i a t i o n / d i s-ease in social thought. This set of identifica-tions is already present in Co m t e, is assumedby Du rkheim, and is transmitted in terms of at h e o retical lineage to functionalist thought.

From my point of view the central issue inthis set of identifications which “e x p e l s” fro mits theoretical nucleus such positivities ashealth, life, or vitality is the institutional issue,or more explicitly, the issue of institutional or-d e r in which is immersed the thought of bothd i s c i p l i n a ry fields (biomedical and social). Al-though the effort at grasping “s u b j e c t i ve mean-i n g s” – or those linked to subjectivity in re l a-tion to phenomena ranging from sickness todeath, or from re c ove ry to cure – seeks a placein some phenomenological or vitalist form u l a-t i o n s, the issue of o rder and deviation (and itsn e c e s s a ry discipline) remains at the epistemo-logical core of grasping these phenomena inthe modern episteme, as demonstrated by Fo u-cault. In this case, how does one secure thet h e o retical positivity of health, the author’sg reat quest in the article at hand, through theidea of a unified theory of health?

From my point of view, theoretically secur-ing a positive conceptualization of health as-sumes the epistemological and institutionald e c o n s t ruction of the disease-illness-sicknesso rd e r, i.e., in the final analysis that of the m e d-ical ord e r.

French socio-anthropology (Du p u y-Ka r s e n-t y, Bo l t a n s k y, He rzlich, and Pierret, among oth-ers) has worked extensively in this direction in

the last thirty ye a r s. To be sure, it was not theobject of the author’s analysis, but it prov i d e san important contribution in the sense of con-s i d e ring this necessary “d e c o n s t ru c t i o n”. Onthe other hand, Bo u rd i e u’s sociological t h o u g h toffers interesting theoretical clues with the cat-e g o ries of f i e l d, h a b i t u s, and p ra c t i c e, in thesense of considering the origin of the theore t i-cal void on health in the biomedical and socialf i e l d s.

Fi n a l l y, as a fifth comment, by way of pos-ing a question, I wish to address the pro p o s a lof a unified theory of health. First: is it possi-ble? Ge n e ral theories assume solidly estab-lished disciplinary fields, with unquestionable“ro o t” concepts (although discussed in term sof their content or interpretation), which isc e rtainly not the case of collective health.

Second, is it desirable? In the life sciencesor social sciences, when a unified theory hasbeen proposed, it has tra versed biology as theunifying basis, which ends up incorporating af a r- f ro m - d e s i rable set of deterministic and va l-u a t i ve pro p o s i t i o n s. I believe that in this case itis better to firmly pri o ri t i ze basic concepts p ro-viding a positive basis for the health issue, tobase it on a set of complementary theories thatthe functionalist Me rton (Social Theory and So-cial St r u c t u re ) called Theories of the Mi d d l eR a n g e. Pe rhaps it might be a matter of conceiv-ing a “g rand theory” in collective health as at h e o retical finishing line and not as a point ofd e p a rt u re.

Instituto de Me d i c i n aS o c i a l , Un i versidade doEstado do Rio de Ja n e i ro,Rio de Ja n e i ro, Bra s i l .

Ju randir Fre i reC o s t a

The article by Naomar Almeida Filho confirm swhat one expects of him. It is ri g o ro u s, clear,i n f o rm a t i ve, intelligent, and open to re f o rm u-lation. It is not easy to outline what might be anall-encompassing theory of health. Howe ve r,his attempt was successful. Hence the idea of adebate is welcome and timely, and above allpays tribute to the author’s effort .

Since the topic is quite lengthy, I will re-s t rict myself to approaching it from a ve ry lim-ited angle, that of the concepts related to thefield. I wish to raise an issue, that of cognitivem o d e l s, in order to hear his opinion.

I believe that the attempt to reconcile theva rious descriptions of the terms disease, dis-o rd e r, illness, sickness, and malady is difficultand extremely complicated. Either one leave s

Page 32: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

ALMEIDA FILHO, N.7 8 4

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

out important aspects of the problem or oneraises the all-encompassing model to such al e vel of abstraction that the formal pre s e n t a-tion becomes acceptable, but debilitated in itsp ractical effects. By practical effects I meanm o re or less clear ru l e s, indicating how to con-duct re s e a rch, evaluate re s u l t s, deal with dis-cussion of the field, etc.

I thus propose renouncing the intention toc o n s t ruct a meta-theory of health in favor ofp rompt descri p t i o n s, subject to revision andf u rther in-depth development. From this per-s p e c t i ve, I believe that we might deri ve theo-retical and practical benefit from dividing thehealth field into two sets, that of physicalist de-s c riptions and that of mentalist descri p t i o n s.In the form e r, we would classify facts postulat-ed as “causally independent” of linguisticmeaning and amenable to being appro a c h e dby quantitative methods, i.e., experi m e n t a lmethods involving control and prediction. T h i sset would include the traditional problems ofbiological medicine at all levels of complexity.In the second we would classify the facts thatwe re “causally dependent on linguistic mean-i n g s”, i.e., all of the “q u a l i t a t i ve”, mentally phe-nomenic aspects of the health experi e n c e. T h i sset would include the facts belonging to thedomains of philosophy, anthro p o l o g y, sociolo-g y, history, genealogy, psyc h o l o g y, etc.

The advantage of this model would be tosimplify possible re s e a rch scripts without re-q u i ring re s e a rchers to undergo the effort ofreconciling investigations from ve ry differe n ta reas of know l e d g e. Under the current state ofhealth re s e a rch, it is extremely difficult to aske x p e rts to have a command over such highlyd i verse are a s. The litera t u re in each field is soe x t e n s i ve that ve ry few are willing or pre p a re dto attempt conciliatory schemata among theo-ries originating from realms of inve s t i g a t i o nthat are so far apart from each other.

The validity of specific investigations wouldbe determined by the canons proper to eacha rea, and the legitimacy of the scientific con-tests in each of them would be evaluated ac-c o rding to independent ethical cri t e ria. Su c hc ri t e ria would be subject to debate among there s e a rchers and community of citizens inter-ested in the subject. Ne ve rt h e l e s s, I suggestthat a general principle be adopted, more orless tacit in medical deontology, as the point ofd e p a rt u re, namely “minimum suffering withmaximum autonomy”. The controversies con-c e rning the meaning of “s u f f e ri n g” or “a u t o n o-my” would be the object of empirical discus-sions or epistemological or linguistic clari f i c a-tion. Based on such a pri n c i p l e, we could judge

at what moment a given discipline was extra p-olating its own field in an ethically legitimatew a y, which would re q u i re a description of thefact cri t i c i zed according to another vo c a b u l a ryor term i n o l o g y.

To grant theoretical autonomy to the re-s e a rch sets means to respect what has alre a d ybeen done, taking better advantage of eacho n e’s critical potential. T h u s, all discussion ofthe “quality of experi e n c e” of health, sickness,d i s e a s e, illness, malady, norm a l i t y, anomaly,e t c. could be challenged, adjusted, corre c t e d ,i m p roved, denied, etc., according to physicalistc o n s t ructions and all nomological descri p t i o nof the same problems would be subject to de-bate according to the forms of knowledge thatseek to offer empirical hypotheses concern i n ga c q u i red beliefs related to the va rious “m e a n-i n g s” of terms like health, sickness, sufferi n g ,a u t o n o m y, etc. The difference between the par-adigms would be respected without our neces-s a rily having to understand “ i n c o m m e n s u ra-bility” as a synonym for “u n t ra n s l a t a b i l i t y ”.

This is the issue in broad term s. If AlmeidaFilho finds it interesting, it would be extre m e l yhelpful to hear what he has to say.

Ce n t ro de Estudios y Asesoría en Salud,Qu i t o, E c u a d o r

Jaime Bre i l h The analysis of the “point of depart u re” to-w a rds a g e n e ral theory of health that Na o m a rAlmeida Filho proposes is not only an urg e n tchallenge for the scientific community, but asubject that demands the combined efforts ofall the social forces now concerned with cari n gfor and developing life.

The time is ri p e, and the level of visibilityhas increased, not only because we are nowbetter equipped with theore t i c a l / e p i s t e m o l o g-ical arg u m e n t s, but because the history of cap-italist modernity has led to a rapid deteri o ra-tion of rights and the loss of all support for es-tablishing a g e n e ral situation of health to re-spond to the expectations of society in genera l.

It is within this context that we should ana-l y ze the importance of the queries raised by thea rticle discussed herein and the value of thec ritical inve n t o ry employed by our re s p e c t e dBrazilian colleague. It is in light of this gre a thuman need and the perplexities of a worldsubmitted to extensive destruction in healththat we ask whether it is now suitable and nec-e s s a ry to spawn a discussion on a g e n e ral theo-

Page 33: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

GENERAL THEORY OF HEALT H 7 8 5

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

ry of health, precisely at a time chara c t e ri ze dby a widespread questioning of “g e n e ral scien-tific fra m e w o rk s” and “m e t a - a c c o u n t s” encom-passing broad interpretations in fields ofk n ow l e d g e. And our answer is emphatically af-f i rm a t i ve. Based on a profound and we l l - i n-f o rmed essay, Naomar Almeida Filho invites usinto a timely and necessary debate. His art i c l ed e m o n s t rates not only his own maturity as ani n vestigator and epistemologist in health, butalso that of the entire Latin American So c i a lMedicine movement, which has provided deci-s i ve contributions from va rious countri e s.

Be yond the possibility of adding new facetsto Almeida Fi l h o’s analysis (and we are familiarwith seve ral such sources from Latin Ameri c athat would doubtless enrich the purposiveconclusion to his paper), we must acknow l e d g eh ow correct he was in fueling the critical flamein the much-needed debate over a general the-o ry of health.

The reading Almeida Filho provides us withon the problem, and that leads him to con-clude with his proposal of “modes of health”,begins and continues with a line of analysiss t rongly linked to the contributions from Eu ro-pean epistemology, and therein lies both thes t rength and importance of his contri b u t i o n ,as well as its limits. The objective of my bri e fc o m m e n t a ry is to outline this strength, as we l las the limits, and highlight the need to incor-p o rate other perspective s.

The importance of Almeida Fi l h o’s contri-bution can be grasped by re t racing the logicalc ycle he follow s, woven around a critical re a d-ing of va rious contributions from sociology,a n t h ro p o l o g y, and epistemology. The entirefirst section of his essay is devoted to display-ing the inability of psycho-biological a p p ro a c h-es to fully deal with the health object, due totheir focus on individual disease processes andtheir negative view of health as the absence ofd i s e a s e, i.e., proposals constituted thro u g hfunctionalist sociology that distinguished be-t ween physical and perc e i ved sickness with thegoal of explaining sickness as the impossibilityof perf o rming personal and organic functions.He also questions the concepts provided byp h e n o m e n o l o g y, centered on the re s t ri c t i ve n o-tion of health as the absence of perc e i ved sick-n e s s. Hence the author’s quest having turn e dt ow a rds the contributions of p s y c h o - c u l t u ra la n t h ro p o l o g y, emphasizing the role of culturein constructing the notion of “s i c k n e s s” (e n f e r-m e d a d) – through a shared language and thecreation of “health/sickness/care” cultural c o m-plexes under the formula sickness = disease +illness (Kleinman), the study of the forms of as-

c ribing meaning and the formation of seman-tic networks (Good & Good), or even the incor-p o ration of social and power relations as deter-minants of the interpre t a t i ve models for sick-ness as an attempt to surmount the micro - s o-cial ( Young). Such approaches we re also cen-t e red on the notion of sickness and cura t i vep ra c t i c e s. And tow a rds the end of his cri t i c a li n ve n t o ry, Almeida Filho reviews the s e m e i o-l o g i c a p p roaches that attempted to ove rc o m ethe micro-social limits of previous lines ofa n a l y s i s, incorporating the analysis of the re l a-tionship between semantic structures and h e g e-monic and power stru c t u res (Good), as well asthe va riants challenging exc e s s i ve part i c u l a re m p h a s i s, proposing the need for a macro - s o-cial historical approach centered on the obser-vation of stru c t u ring collective conditions andconditioning experiences that combine in sys-tems of “s i g n s, meanings, and practices inh e a l t h” that do not obey We s t e rn medical logicand that appear as non-stable and diffuse pro-totypes (Bibeau & Co rin). Almeida Filho re c o g-n i zes that this latter view not only continues tobe framed in the notion of sickness, but that ite x p resses a certain anti-naturalism that leave saside the pro b l e m’s biological material ele-m e n t s.

At this point our author launches into thequest for a ve ritable epistemology of healtht h rough an analysis of Ge o rges Ca n g u i l h e m’sthought. He analyzes the French epistemolo-g i s t’s proposals of considering normality as alife norm that incorporates the healthy and thepathological, where by health is not considere dsimply the obedience to a norm or model,since disobedience and deviation are part ofhealth, and approaching the discussion of thisf ree and unconditional “philosophical health”that is forged in physicians’ praxeological sce-n a rio with their patients and is also pro j e c t e dinto a public health linked to the notions ofu t i l i t y, quality of life, and happiness, a pro c e s sthat is finally re a l i zed in the phenotype and iso b s e rva b l e. Almeida Filho re c o g n i zes the im-p o rtance of a Canguilhemian opening tow a rd sa new epistemology, yet cri t i c i zes the pre m i s ethat this vision is linked fundamentally to thebiological, despite recognizing “that health isnot only life in the silence of the organs... but al-so life in the silence of social re l a t i o n s” and thatscientific health should assimilate aspects ofs u b j e c t i ve and philosophical individual healthin such a way that it is not reduced to sicknessand so-called “ri s k s”.

In short, through his epistemological tour,Almeida Filho has succeeded first of all in clari-fying the inability of psycho-biological and

Page 34: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

ALMEIDA FILHO, N.7 8 6

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

p s yc h o - c u l t u ral models to ove rcome the nega-t i ve definitions and solve “Ka n t’s pro b l e m” ofthis resistance against conceptualizing healthin and of itself, and secondly in re t rieving thepotential of Ca n g u i l h e m’s opening, but signal-ing its focus on the biological terrain, just asFo u c a u l t’s explanation was oriented tow a rd sm e rely social and discursive explanations.

In the final, purposive section, Almeida Fi-lho turns to the contribution of Juan Sa m a j a ,with his idea of multiple determination withh i e ra rchical interf a c e s, an important LatinA m e rican line of reflection that adds to otherc o n t ributions that have opened the doors to ani n t e g ral conceptualization.

Within these brief comments, we do not in-tend to develop a profound analysis of the“modes of health” proposals or its basis on theidea of hiera rchical interf a c e s, since this meri t se l a b o ration that we are incorporating into oth-er art i c l e. The point here is first to highlight thevalue of the pathway that Almeida Filho hascalled us to follow and the germ i n a t i ve poten-tial of some of his ideas for epistemologicalw o rk in the coming ye a r s. Howe ve r, secondly,we are interested in identifying here some ofthe limitations of his approach, as well as anu n re s o l ved epistemological problem that is notvisible in his analysis, despite its import a n c e,n a m e l y, what he would refer to as resistance to-w a rds the collective .

Epistemology and history teach us that inS c i e n c e, the processes of conceptual cleansingp roposed from an emancipatory perspectivea re closely linked to the need for practical ad-vances in collectives that develop their pro c e s sin the midst of hegemony, are full of intention-ality and conditioned by the hori zon of visibili-ty and their social contextualization, a hori zo nthat depends extensively on epistemic condi-tions – in the Foucaultian sense – as well as thep ractical articulations of the scientific. In thiss e n s e, we ask whether the only “point of depar-t u re” or take-off in the critical process is thei nve n t o ry of contributions from Eu ro p e a nthought, or if there is not a need to think outour own model and orient our reflections be-yond this single point of view, within an inter-c u l t u ral construction and the perspective ofc ritical multicultura l i s m .

While the construction of a scientific dis-course on health in genera l is an academic is-s u e, it invo l ves intellectual work and a pra c t i c ethat go beyond the limits of academe, but w h i c ha re part of the construction of know l e d g e.

To orient the current work, we need to clar-ify its nature, content, and direction, and this isnot possible. At least from a democratic and in-

t e g ral perspective, this can only be done fro mthe scientific community and based on a visioni n s p i red exc l u s i vely by the cardinal pro b l e m sand points of growth established by Eu ro p e a ne p i s t e m o l o g y, no matter how important thelatter may be.

To establish what we are re f e r ring to whenwe speak of a general theory of health, i.e. ,what the difference is between a broad and in-n ova t i ve theory and a matrix, unilateral, andhegemonic account – and to analyze who wea re calling on for such an undertaking, it isn e c e s s a ry to call other societal perspectives in-to the debate, and this is not only a logistic,p ractical problem, but also a theoretical one.Fu rt h e rm o re, from a praxeological focus, ag e n e ral theory not only defines the object o ft ra n s f o rmation in a scientific field, but also thes u b j e c t of said tra n s f o rmation, and the two gohand in hand, since they are interd e p e n d e n telements of know l e d g e. Stated differe n t l y, wep resuppose here that if a theory cannot be re-duced to a reflection induced in thought, norcan it be a simple deduction of reality based ona rational model, then a general theory of h e a l t hshould encompass the historical subjects mo-b i l i zed around the object as a field of action –in this case the field of health – both as theb roadest of processes that constitute its com-plex object and with its hiera rchical domains,with its macro - m i c ro and social-biological ar-t i c u l a t i o n s.

As Latour (1999) would explain metaphori-c a l l y, the idea of a separation between thew o rld (o u t s i d e) and the mind (i n s i d e) that isp resent in the form of both positivist objec-tivism and that of rationalism and phenome-nology allowed for the creation of the notion ofan “o b j e c t i ve world”, unreachable for the c o m-mon people below; and this false disjunctionmade it possible to impose the power of cold,scientific reason, outside of a human collectives t i g m a t i zed as an irrational mass.

The construction of a new basis for a gener-al theory of health that Almeida Filho calls usto reflect on cannot be achieved through thisopen or disguised polarization between the“s u b j e c t”, the “o b j e c t i ve world”, and the “m a s s”,but from a praxeological view that dissolve ssuch a polarity and re c overs the human side ofscientific practice and its profound re l a t i o n swith the collective. As expressed by the S c i e n-tific Institute of Indigenous Cu l t u re s of the Co n-f e d e ration of Indians of Ec u a d o r, it is part ofthe struggle for “d i versity with equity. . . within ac o n t ext of political democra c y, social justice,and economic equality” ( I CCI, 2001), the ur-gency to construct life and health as an an-

Page 35: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

GENERAL THEORY OF HEALT H 7 8 7

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

t i t h e s i s, which are expressed outside the worldof academe and form the best interpelationc o n c e rning the meaning of science.

I CCI (Instituto Científico de Cu l t u ras In d í g e n a s ) ,2001. Ed i t o rial. Boletín ICCI-RIMAI, 24.

LATOUR, B., 1999. Pa n d o ra’s Ho p e : Essays on the Re-ality of Science St u d i e s. Ca m b ridge: Ha rva rd Un i-versity Pre s s.

D é p a rtement d’ An t h ro p o l o g i e ,Un i versité de Mo n t r é a l ,Mo n t r é a l , Ca n a d a .

Gilles Bi b e a u In defense of a cre o l i zed grammar of the health-disease complex

“The culture of any society at any time is morelike the debris, or fall-out, of past ideologicals y s t e m s , than it is itself a system, a cohere n tw h o l e . C o h e rent wholes may exist (but thesetend to be lodged in individual heads, s o m e-times in those of obsessives and para n o i a c s ) ,b u thuman social groups tend to find their opennessto the future in the variety of their metaphorsfor what may be the good life and in the contex tof their para d i g m s” (Victor Tu rn e r, 1974:14).

The perspective I favor in my response toProfessor Naomar Almeida Filho borrows firstf rom work in the anthropology of science pro-duced by Latour (1999) and Hacking (1999) andsecond from my own experience as a re s e a rc h e rin the area of medical anthro p o l o g y, a sub-disci-pline that emerged from studies conducted pri-m a rily in non-We s t e rn societies during the colo-nial era. In those days anthropologists we re busyp o rt raying particular beliefs (witchcraft, sor-c e ry, magic) invented by people to explain mis-f o rt u n e s, disasters, and diseases, and descri b-ing therapeutic rituals (spirit possession, magi-cal devices, anti-sorc e ry ceremonies) that heal-ers applied to treat particular episodes of the dis-ease-illness-sickness complex. Few anthro p o l o-gists have shown a keen interest in deve l o p i n gan anthropology of health as a counterwe i g h tto the “disease perspective” canonized by clas-sical medical anthro p o l o g y. Only recently havea n t h ropologists begun to consider the issue ofhealth and well-being as a topic which deserve sfull attention. The essay by Professor de Almei-da Filho is a timely contribution from whichmedical anthropologists should greatly benefit.

I begin by briefly stating my stance as amedical anthropologist. In my view, humans inall societies are confronted with the same fun-damental “existential problems” and “anxie t i e s”,

like the awareness of the inevitability of death( m o rt u a ry rituals and after-death cults to thed e p a rted), the origins of evil, suffering, anddisease (magic ri t u a l s, religious cere m o n i e s ) ,and difficulty in maintaining harm o n y, cooper-ation, and well-being. Human societies re-sponded to these challenges by combining twos e ries of re p re s e n t a t i o n s, ideas, and pra c t i c e s :(a) a symbolic idiom built around basic mimet-ic (metaphorical and metonymic) pro c e s s e swhich helped them assign meaning to their af-flictions and (b) an empiri c a l l y- o riented atti-tude that eventually gave birth to what we nowcall science. Ritual healing practices have de-veloped at the interface between the symbolicidiom and the pragmatic effort to tame the“ b a d” via the use of plants, cura t i ve interve n-t i o n s, and other re p a ra t i ve techniques. T h ro u g h-out the millennia, the search for meaning andthe dri ve for knowledge have served as pointsof depart u re for further theoretical elabora-tions in the va rious cultures which all ended upinventing their own therapeutic systems, a m o n gwhich one finds We s t e rn medicine.

I agree with philosophers and historians ofscience who have amply demonstrated in re-cent decades that scientific facts, theori e s, andconcepts are value-laden and that medical, p s y-chological, and socio-anthropological know l-edge on either health or disease is cultura l l yand historically constructed. Ex p e rts in thee t h n o g raphy of science have shown that allf o rms of knowledge are largely context-depen-dent products rather than transcendent re a l i-t i e s, and that the pre valent We s t e rn litera t u rein contempora ry biology, medicine, psyc h i a t ry,and health-related social sciences tend both tob ring particular theoretical fra m e w o rk s, cate-g o ri e s, and models to the fore f ront and to sup-p ress or silence altern a t i ve ways to assess, in-t e r p ret, name, and theori ze certain areas suchas the health/well-being complex. Me a n w h i l e,c ritical social scientists insist that the pro d u c-tion of knowledge is never neutral, that there isno such thing as a “m e re fact” or an evidence-based theory, and that scholars, intellectuals,and theory-builders themselves are inevitablylinked to a particular ideology or set of beliefs.

By combining a socio-anthropological di-mension with linguistic, semantic, and episte-mological considera t i o n s, Professor AlmeidaFilho has established a solid foundation for de-lineating a theory of health which incorpora t e sall major elements put at work in the doubles t ra t e g y, namely the beliefs systems and thescientific response to which humans re s o rtw h e re ver and whenever they face misfort u n e,d i s e a s e, and other sorts of pro b l e m s. I enthusi-

Page 36: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

ALMEIDA FILHO, N.7 8 8

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

astically support the line of argument pro-posed by Professor Almeida Filho in his chal-lenging essay. To org a n i ze my own thinkingabout what a theory of health is, I found it use-ful to explore five areas: the “p e rfect health”i d e o l o g y; biology as a historical and interper-sonal script; humans as producers of languagesand idioms of health-distress; the life of peop l ein multiple worlds; and local epistemologies.I feel that all these five domains should bec o ns i d e red as necessary and complementarys o u rces in the theorization of the health do-main. I conclude my own questioning by askingwhether there is room for theory in modern sci-e n c e. The path I decided to take leads exactlyw h e re Professor Almeida Filho was heading:c o n c e n t rating on health rather than diseaseand introducing local epistemologies in thec o n s t ruction of a general theory of health.

The quest for “p e rfect health”

The “well-being complex” has been installed asa key symbol in We s t e rn culture, particularly inc o u n t ries of the No rt h e rn hemisphere: tech-niques of all sorts and a rh e t o ric of persuasion( e.g., from body massage to religious enro l l-ment) are currently used to discipline the bodyand regulate individual life styles. In cert a i nc o n t e x t s, the therapist-patient relationship hasalso been tra n s f o rmed into a continuous andl o n g - t e rm relationship for body management(clinical surveillance or regular check-ups tove rify the results of treatment), giving rise to ag rowing “c a re industry” which has colonize dthe health domain by medicalizing social andp s ychological conditions which have to do w i t hthe ve ry fact that a person exists. One can easi-ly find multiple examples in both industrial na-tions and the developing world of medical tech-nologies aimed at controlling deviant behavior( h y p e ra c t i ve children, drug addiction, etc.), aswell as plagues, diseases, and even natural lifec ycle events (childbirth, menopause, etc.).

Such heavy reliance on healing techniquesfor the body and mind reflects one of the cen-t ral concerns of our era: the achievement of a“p e rfect health” status. The pharmaceutical in-d u s t ry spends billions on re s e a rch into tre a t-ments for such problems as obesity and ove r-weight, baldness, wri n k l e s, acne, depre s s i o n ,and impotence, leading to a “life style dru gm a rk e t” that induces people to fantasize aboutthe perfect body, mood, and mind. All this re-i n f o rces people’s dependence on “e x p e rt s” ofva rious vintages and on the multiplication ofmedical techniques geared to reestablish equi-l i b rium and repair the body-mind complex.

In the past, medicine’s role was to heal thehuman body from sickness. In our age, medicaltechnologies aim to do much more: modernmedicine is, intentionally, total re c ove ry, org a nt ra n s p l a n t s, cosmetics, and self-help re h a b i l i-tation. While modern medical technologies cane f f e c t i vely cure the sick body, it also claims toalter the body and mind in such ways as to im-p rove perf o rm a n c e, pre s e rve youth, achievei m m o rt a l i t y, reduce or eliminate gender differ-e n t i a l s, and eventually reach the utopia of“p e rfect health”. Based on these pre m i s e s, pre-vention has become a massive technologicale n t e r p ri s e, often involving sophisticated andcostly genetic prediction pro c e d u re s, and re i n-f o rcing dependence on scientific technologies,but also creating more ethical dilemmas andg rowing contra d i c t i o n s.

Bi o l o gy as a historical and interpersonal scri p t

We have entered an era dominated by a new bi-ology that links the brain-mind complex to en-v i ronment and history, both at collective andindividual leve l s. The schism introduced inm o d e rn biology by De s c a rt e s’ dualism of mindand brain has been thrown to the wind: newways are emerging to perc e i ve the body, themind, the emotions, and the health-diseasecomplex. The mechanistic philosophy whichused to see the body as a machine is visiblydead (or dying): contempora ry (neuro ) b i o l o g yis based on the indissoluble relationship be-t ween the person’s life experience and themodeling of his/her biological memory, theh i s t o rical shaping of individual neuro l o g i c a la rc h i t e c t u re, the coding of neural network salong with one’s personal history, and the bio-p s ycho-social dynamics of higher conscious-n e s s. Biology is thus seen as dynamic, interper-sonal, historical, and evo l u t i o n a ry. In d i v i d u a le x p e riences constantly inform the biologicaln e t w o rks and provoke rapid and eve r- c h a n g-ing patterns in the neurological codes. In d i v i d-ual histories shape brain and mind simultane-o u s l y; the brain and mind are indissolublylinked to each another and to the person’s ac-tual history.

Ne u ro s c i e n t i s t s, evo l u t i o n a ry psyc h o l o-g i s t s, and biological anthropologists genera l l ya g ree that individual neurological maps areboth historically and environmentally pro-duced. Ne u ral codes are formed through: “u n emise en correspondance entre , d’une part , u nétat de choses ex t é r i e u r, un objet, une situation,et d’ a u t re part une organisation neuronale etl’état d’activité qui l’inve s t i t” (Changeux, 1998:113). T h u s, differences in the epigenetic deve l-

Page 37: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

GENERAL THEORY OF HEALT H 7 8 9

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

opment of persons (particularly in the familye n v i ronment) contribute to differences in theo rganization of each individual’s biological ar-c h i t e c t u re. It is true that the more we knowabout the interactions between genetic andnon-genetic factors, the more complicatedthese interactions appear to be: the ways inwhich “c a u s a t i o n” functions are often far fro mself-evident, and a number of feedback loops,both positive and negative, are constantly atw o rk. The accepted explanation of “c a u s a t i o n”f rom genes to culture, as from genes to anyother human phenomenon, is neither exc l u-s i vely here d i t a ry nor exc l u s i vely enviro n m e n-tal: it is interaction between the two. This is al-so common knowledge among people in mostc u l t u res around the world.

Ne ve rt h e l e s s, the “ h i s t o ri c a l l y- g ro u n d e dbiological model” has weaknesses: it discard swhat people do with what they pro d u c e, themeanings they attach to their local pro d u c-t i o n s, and the experiences they construct. It isnot surprising that scholars who examine hu-man phenomena from the perspective of per-sons consider the “ h i s t o rical scri p t” in biologyto be reductionist, animal-dri ven, and still ex-c e s s i vely deterministic, despite its effort toove rcome past dualisms, like that proposed byDe s c a rt e s. Undoubtedly there is still significantmisunderstanding between historically andc u l t u rally minded biologists and social scien-t i s t s, but much has been done to narrow gapsf rom the past. It is now possible to move be-yond the past opposition to establish solid,balanced cooperation between the socio-cul-t u ral and biodynamic para d i g m s, in a part n e r-ship in which both perspectives are equallyvalued and respected. Professor Almeida Fi l h oadds to this line of thought a strong interest inthe meaning-based and experiential dimen-sion of the health-disease complex.

Humans as producers of languages and idioms of health-distre s s

Language is the function that chara c t e ri zes thespecies (Homo sapiens sapiens) as distinct fro mp recursor primate systems of communication:it is emblematic of a universally stru c t u red hu-man mind, the same in all places and times.Chomsky has demonstrated that all humanlanguages share certain universal feature s,both at the syntactic level of grammatical cate-g o ries and at the phonological level of sounds.He argues that there is a Un i versal Gra m m a rwhich is linked to the fact that humans areequipped with the same innately pro g ra m m e dcapacity for language, re p resentation, and s y m-

bolization. Like the complexity of language it-self, the capacity to re p resent (signifier- s i g n i-fied) and to symbolize (minimally the mimeticfaculty) is seen as being intrinsic to the neuro-logical organization of the brain and to thefunctioning of the mind; in parallel, re p re s e n-tational and symbolic capabilities are said tobe linked to the linguistic ability that defineshuman beings. One may draw two conclusionsf rom these observations: (a) probably beyo n dall these phenomena, there exists a meta-s t ru c t u re (consciousness?) which is thoro u g h l yo rg a n i zed in the form of a language; (b) all oth-er physical, mental, and symbolic capacitiesa re also constituted as built-in pro g rams andmay thus be seen as translating this same lin-g u i s t i c a l l y-shaped meta-stru c t u re.

Human beings build diverse and sophisti-cated culture s. Co n t ra ry to non-human pri-m a t e s, human beings are not only equipped top roduce language: they actually speak one (ormany) language(s) and assign meanings, gen-e rating multiple narra t i ves and stories on thebasis of the grammar(s) they master. In addi-tion to languages, human groups invent mythsand cosmologies which provide blueprints toi n t e r p ret the world in which they live, ideolo-g i e s, belief systems, and moral norms whichtend to va ry (probably around a universal core )f rom society to society as well as particular so-cial rules (family pattern s, inter- g roup re l a-tions) which serve as a foundation for con-s t ructing the ways “to be a person” in a give ns o c i e t y. All these ingredients compose what an-t h ropologists refer to as a “c u l t u re”. Our moder-nity is constituted, as any other culture, as theensemble of narra t i ve s, stori e s, and experi-ences that people generate on the basis of theva l u e s, norm s, symbols, and myths shaping thec o n t e m p o ra ry world.

In their study of narra t i ves and experi e n c e sp roduced by individuals, many social scientistsin recent years have adopted an interpre t i veand phenomenological stance which borrow smuch from semeiology, litera ry criticism, andEu ropean existential phenomenology. Me r-l e a u - Ponty was one of the leaders in the post-war industrial world of a movement to re n e wphilosophy – initiated by Husserl with phe-nomenology – that invo l ved a new re l a t i o n s h i pb e t ween body and mind, a topic that had re-mained unchallenged since De s c a rt e s. Me r-l e a u - Po n t y ’s phenomenology does not envi-sion the body-mind as a duality, nor as a di-c h o t o m y, but rather as the translation (expre s-sion) of a “double nature”: corporeality re t u rn sh e re in the form of a ve h i c l e, leaving room formeaningful experiences that persons are able

Page 38: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

ALMEIDA FILHO, N.7 9 0

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

both to live and to put into word s. Di s c o u r s e s,n a r ra t i ve s, and complaints that persons phra s eto express their emotions are inevitably shapedby the idioms provided by the culture(s) towhich they belong.

For seve ral decades social scientists havea rgued against all sorts of reductionist theori e sthat attempt to model the study of persons andhuman cultures (including human health) onan animal model. They have reminded theirbiomedical colleagues that the problem of sig-nification (meaning) is tied to human beings’self-definition and that the practice of humansciences thus re q u i res the inclusion of semeiol-ogy and herm e n e u t i c s. Human beings are on-tological beings who cannot avoid interpre t i n gt h e m s e l ve s, others, and the world. “Human be-ings are self-interpreting animals”, anthro p o l o-gists write re p e a t e d l y, echoing a central themein contempora ry social sciences.

I firmly believe it is important, as Pro f e s s o rAlmeida Filho does in a convincing way, to ex-amine specific interrelations between c o l l e c-t i ve meaning systems, l o c a l idioms of health-d i s t re s s, and i n d i v i d u a l discourses of we l l - b e-ing and pain, that is, to know how people expe-rience and express emotions and how theyconnect somatic symptoms with their innerp s ychological states. This re q u i res a critical re-view of past and current hypotheses of howsymptoms are produced, constructed, and ex-p e rienced by different peoples or cultures un-der va rying social, material, political, and psy-chological conditions.

To date, re s e a rch on idioms of health-dis-t ress has emphasized the ways such idioms areshaped by cultural taxo n o m i e s, explanatorym o d e l s, and popular semeiologies, at times ne-glecting the social context in which the personl i ves and the person’s spatial position – in m a n ycases – at the boundaries between multiplec u l t u ral worlds. Anthro p o l o g i c a l l y- m i n d e dp s yc h i a t rists and psychologists also favor ele-ments within a person that can be connectedto categories such as “symptom schemes”, “ i l l-ness schemes”, and “idioms of distre s s”.

Besides meaning, two other important no-t i o n s, namely narrativization and experi e n c e,a re attached to the perspective opened by thephenomenological and interpre t i ve turn ofmedical social sciences. It is not enough to saythat people act tow a rds things in at least par-tial congruence with the meanings these thingshold for them. People also produce discourses,commentaries, and narratives in which they t e l l ,via complex rh e t o rical stra t e g i e s, the meaningsassociated with their experiences and behav-i o r s. Their idioms of health-distress and their

health-illness explanatory models and s c h e m e sa re also largely dependent on their systems ofmeaning. To be properly understood, the va ri-ous narra t i ves and idioms have to be insert e dwithin a series of other discourses and ulti-mately placed in the larger context of the cul-t u re which supports these texts. We must takeinto account the fact that human speakers in-c o r p o rate cultural presuppositions into theirn a r ra t i ve s, that the blank spaces of discoursesa re loaded with meanings, and that any re a d-ing limited to the surface runs the risk of miss-ing the cultural dimension. The stress put onn a r rativization is sometimes so strong in con-t e m p o ra ry medical social sciences that somes c h o l a r s, particularly medical anthro p o l o g i s t s,h a ve come to see culture as nothing more thana mega-text.

People today stand on the boundaries of many wo rl d s

In almost all modern countri e s, one finds thecoexistence of multiple languages, re l i g i o n s,and culture s. The dialectic notions of centerand peri p h e ry, inclusion and exclusion, major-ity and minority are commonly used by socialscientists to study the dynamics of cultura lp owe r, cultural pluralism, hegemony and dom-i n a n c e, control and submission, and the re l a-tions that either oppose or link the va rious so-cial groups in a given society. Most people to-day live on the boundaries between groups anddefine themselves as persons with multiple af-f i l i a t i o n s. It appears particularly urgent to tack-le the challenges created by the impact of suchp l u ralistic societies (many re l i g i o n s, languages,and cultures) on both individuals and families.Co g n i t i ve maps, va l u e s, and systems of mean-ing are re o rg a n i zed to fit the pluralist context,with vacuums and cracks in their midst. Re c e n tre s e a rch fra m e w o rks take into account thec o n t radictions and tensions emerging from thep l u ralistic situations in which individuals andg roups live. Cre o l i zed versions of cultural sys-tems have emerged on all continents, and citi-zens of most countries are there f o re torn be-t ween multiple parallel attachments, whilepeople eve ry w h e re are trapped between fideli-ty to one’s cultural identity and the need to as-sume a more flexible pluralist frame of re f e r-ence (Bibeau, 1997).

The ethnic, linguistic, re l i g i o u s, and cultur-al pluralism which was already present in thevast majority of countries is greatly accelera t e dby migration, displacement, and refugee move-ments across national borders and by the factthat countries are increasingly permeable to

Page 39: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

GENERAL THEORY OF HEALT H 7 9 1

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

influences from abroad. In most countri e s, p e o-ple are forced to confront more and more am-b i g u i t y, with multiple group affiliations and hy-b rid identification models at the edges of theirc u l t u ral worlds. The dominant challenge in allp l u ralist societies is to build collective cultura lre f e rence systems that combine the local withthe global and community- g rounded va l u e swith a common sense of belonging.

In their comments on the interpre t i ve turnthat human sciences have taken since the mid-1 9 7 0 s, Ra b i n ow & Su l l i van (1985:35) wro t e :“Common meanings are the basis of communi-t y. In t e r- s u b j e c t i ve meaning gives a people acommon language to talk about social re a l i t yand a common understanding of certain norms,but only with common meanings does this com-mon re f e rence world contain significant com-mon actions, c e l e b ra t i o n s , and feelings. T h e s ea re objects in the world that eve rybody share s .This is what makes community”. In t e r- s u b j e c-t i ve meanings are not only located in theminds of people, but are also incorporated ande x p ressed in their collective practices and con-stituted as social actions. Only a direct experi-ence of the world of others provides a sense ofp re - c o m p rehension about the meanings peo-ple attach to their behaviors and actions. T h i simplies that re s e a rchers must become familiarwith the world of others (natural settings) ande x p e rience it at least partially if they want to beable to grasp something of the world in whichpeople live. All this becomes more complexwhen people start living in multiple para l l e lworlds as in contempora ry societies.

Local epistemologies as a source for theori z i n g

We know that indicators (mark e r s, signs, symp-toms) used by people to identify actual healthp roblems as well as lay explanatory systems donot exist as explicitly conceptualized bodies ofk n owledge that can be easily reconstituted andt ra n s f o rmed into a sort of textbook of “p o p u l a rp a t h o l o g y ”. Such knowledge is rather enactedand manifested in the actual behaviors of peo-ple (patients, families, community gro u p s )when they are faced with concrete cases. I feelthat any exploration into theory in the health-disease complex must consider at least the fol-l owing three series of data: (a) the local re p re-s e n t a t i o n s, ideas and practices developed tosee the world, to be a person, to conduct a va l u-able life, to produce well-being, to organize t i m eand space, and to relate to material pro g re s s ;(b) the indigenous values related to the body-mind, to the health-disease complex and to thes p i ritual aspects of human life; and (c) the

k n owledge re g a rding the natural, physical, andsocial as well as psychological, spiritual, andc u l t u ral dimensions of the world in which indi-viduals and groups live. Professor Almeida Fi l-h o’s theorization of health and disease is pre-cisely based on a compre h e n s i ve appro a c hthat includes social and cultural traditions aswell as local systems of know l e d g e.

O rd i n a ry people have learned that re s p o n s-es provided by health professionals and “e x-p e rt s” cannot suffice to alleviate their pro b-lems and that sustainable solutions re q u i re al-liances between locally-based interve n t i o n sand professional actions and, more globally, at rue integration between the values and pra c-tices of people and formal professional pra c-t i c e s. Locally produced, collective healing re-sponses have a greater chance of matching theneeds and actual problems as experienced byindividuals and gro u p s. As a note of caution,h owe ve r, while I acknowledge the re l e vance ofsuch community-based lay know l e d g e, I s h o u l dalso re c o g n i ze its own constraints and limita-t i o n s. Professor Almeida Filho is, I think, on theright track when he looks for an implicit theoryin the different systems of signs, meaning, andp ra c t i c e s.

Is there any place for theory in modern science?

Professor Naomar Almeida Filho is aware,p robably more than anyone else, that moder-nity is usually associated with seculari z a t i o n ,the idea of pro g re s s, the dominion of facts, thesystematization of knowledge in general, andthe rise of “s c i e n c e”. A strong reliance on sci-e n c e, (art i ) f a c t s, and data has been – and still is– a totem of the modern We s t e rn approach tothe world. T h e re is no doubt that the Bra z i l i a np rofessor fully agrees with Max Weber when here f e r red to the tra j e c t o ry of modern thought asthe “disenchantment of the world” and thus toits de-theorization. Despite such evidence,Professor Almeida Filho argues that scienceneeds theory in order to be complete. The ri s eand dominance of new forms of science (biolo-g y, medicine, psyc h i a t ry, anthro p o l o g y, psy-c h o l o g y, and sociology) have actually led to thep reeminence of certain conceptual models forthe ways people’s health, suffering, pain, andd i s t ress are commonly constructed by clini-c i a n s, medical expert s, and social scientists. Inthis respect, contempora ry biomedical scienceis responsible for the creation of taxonomies ofdisease that are assumed universal, va l u e - f re e,and autonomous from history and culture. Allthis is clearly stated in Almeida Fi l h o’s essay.

Page 40: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

ALMEIDA FILHO, N.7 9 2

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

Professor Naomar Almeida Filho has alsomapped, with an excellent knowledge of cur-rent debates, the new terri t o ry explored by his-t o ri a n s, sociologists, and anthropologists whoh a ve argued that both the subjective experi-ence and subsequent recognition, labeling,and interpretation of the health-distre s s - d i s-ease complex are socially and culturally pro-duced (Bibeau, 1995, 1997; Bibeau & Co ri n ,1994; Foucault, 1966; Good, 1994; Kleinman,1988; Young, 1995). These re s e a rchers adva n c e dthe idea that re p re s e n t a t i o n s, va l u e s, and con-cepts concerning health and disease are in-evitably created within a context of multiplef o rms of knowledge which are as much g ro u n d-ed in local epistemologies as they are linked tothe scholarly academic world. These forms ofk n owledge affect the ways by which the life-worlds of persons are built and design the ar-c h i t e c t u re of that fuzzy area cove red by whatsocial scientists name, with some hesitation,the health-disease-illness-sickness complex. Inother word s, following Hacking (1995), “s t y l e sof re a s o n i n g” are integral to both medical dis-course and the cultura l l y- f ramed ideas builta round the health-disease complex. Anthro-pologists have also demonstrated that these“styles of re a s o n i n g” va ry in important waysa c ross disciplines in academia and accord i n gto different social and cultural settings.

Professor Naomar Almeida Filho has inve s-tigated, with great scru t i n y, heuristic conceptssuch as “styles of re a s o n i n g”, “local epistemolo-g i e s”, “systems of signs, meaning, and practices”,and “t ra n s d i s c i p l i n a ri t y ”, with the intent of for-mulating the groundwork for a general theory of(public) health. He has courageously navigatedon troubled seas, on the ones tra veled by med-ical sociologists and anthropologists who ove rthe past three to four decades have emphasize dthe socio-cultural dimensions of the health-dis-ease complex, and as well on other seas, eve nm o re dangero u s, explored by the promoters ofc ritical epistemology in contempora ry social,c u l t u ral, and medical sciences. Howe ve r, thetime for celebrating the achievements of tra n s-d i s c i p l i n a ry collaboration has not yet come,contends Almeida Fi l h o, particularly when oneexamines the paucity of theories deve l o p e da round the “s u bs t a n c e” of what is health. T h e reis still much fragmentation in the pro d u c t i o nof know l e d g e, and theory-building is still a po-tential proposition, far from being implement-ed in re a l i t y, although biomedical and health-related social scientists have begun to prov i d enew conceptual fra m e w o rks for assessing hu-man phenomena, particularly phenomena as-sociated with health and disease.

Professor Almeida Filho has argued that itis through the evaluation of fra m e s, models,and practices commonly used in science (bybiomedical and health-related social scientists)that we will eventually gain a better understand-ing of how suffering, distre s s, and pain are tra n s-f o rmed into nosographic categories and eve n t u-ally absorbed into the scientific domain. He al-so notes that it is essential to promote a gre a t e rh e t e rogeneity of models, theori e s, and conceptsas a counterweight to the increasing homoge-nization of disease-oriented knowledge and the-o ry. The perspective that I have explored in myresponse calls on us all to seriously considerthe way ord i n a ry people construct their ow nmodels of health and disease. The people I knowall live on the boundaries of many worlds andc o n s t ruct their re p resentations of the health-dis-ease complex in re f e rence to a creole gra m m a r.Any theory of health and well-being should takefull consideration of this fundamental fact. AndI feel that anthropologist Victor Turner (1974:14)was correct when he wrote that “human socialg roups tend to find their openness to the futurein the va riety of their metaphors for what maybe the good life and in the context of their para-d i g m s”. T h e o ries are embedded in re s p o n s e ssocieties develop to produce “the good life”.

B I B E AU, G., 1997 Cu l t u ral psyc h i a t ry in a cre o l i z i n gworld: Questions for a new re s e a rch agenda.Tra n s c u l t u ral Ps y c h i a t ry, 34:9-41.

B I B E AU, G. & CORIN, E., 1995. Beyond Tex t u a l i t y. As-ceticism and Violence in An t h ropological In t e r p re-t a t i o n. Berlin: Mouton de Gru y t e r.

CHANGEUX, J.-P. & RICOEUR, P., 1998. La Na t u re etla Règle. Ce qui nous fait Pe n s e r. Pa ris: ÉditionsOdile Ja c o b.

CORIN, E., 1994. The social and cultural matrix of healthand disease. In: Why are Some People Healthy andOthers Not? The Determinants of Health of Po p u l a-t i o n s (R. G. Eva n s, M. L. Ba rer & T. R. Ma rmot, ed.),p p. 93-132, New Yo rk: Aldine de Gru y t e r.

F O U C AU LT, M., 1966. Les Mots et les Choses. Une ar-chéologie des Sciences Hu m a i n e s. Pa ris: Ga l l i m a rd .

G O O D, B., 1994. Me d i c i n e , R a t i o n a l i t y, and Ex p e r i-e n c e . An An t h ropological Pe r s p e c t i ve. Ca m b ri d g e :Ca m b ridge Un i versity Pre s s.

H ACKING, I., 1999. The Social Construction of W h a t ?Ca m b ridge: Ha rva rd Un i versity Pre s s.

KLEINMAN, A., 1988. The Illness Na r ra t i ve s . Su f f e r-i n g , Healing & the Human Condition. New Yo rk :Basic Bo o k s.

LATOUR, B., 1999. Pa n d o ra’s Ho p e . Essays on the Re-ality of Science St u d i e s. Ca m b ridge: Ha rva rd Un i-versity Pre s s.

R A B I N OW, P. & SULLIVAN, W. M., 1979. In t e r p re t i veSocial Science. A Re a d e r. Be rkeley/Los Angeles/London: Un i versity of Ca l i f o rnia Pre s s.

YOUNG, A., 1995. The Harmony of Il l u s i o n s . In ve n t-ing Po s t - Traumatic St ress Di s o rd e r. Pri n c e t o n :Princeton Un i versity Pre s s.

Page 41: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

GENERAL THEORY OF HEALT H 7 9 3

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

Local epistemologies and general theory of health: a rebuttal

The commentary by Ro b e rto Bri c e ñ o - L e ó ns h ows profound skepticism as to the feasibilityor even validity of a proposal to conceptuallyd e velop the health object in the direction of aGe n e ral T h e o ry of Health (One of the otherc o m m e n t a ries defends a position similar tothat of Briceño-León but includes a set of non-systematic and impressionistic pro p o s i t i o n son the health theme, without even re f e r ring tothe content of the essay under debate. In saidc o m m e n t a ry, the use of concepts is quite idio-s y n c ratic and disconnected from the theore t i-cal schemata I have analyzed, thus hinderi n gits incorporation into the present line of de-b a t e. I thus lack a basis for incorporating it intothis rebuttal).

Be f o re analyzing the content of Bri c e ñ o -L e ó n’s cri t i q u e, I should point out some misun-derstandings I find in this commentary: in mya rt i c l e, I did not appeal to the concept of sick-ness to define health, did not propose any defi-nition of health, and did not state that healthwas something that is lost. Briceño-León pur-p o rtedly agrees with Gadamer (1996) by takinghealth as a feeling, a living experi e n c e, an ef-fect of subjectivity, an element of individualimagination. He contends that sickness consti-tutes a social construct, while health would bea construct “located in the shifting terrain ofd e s i re”. I cannot agree with such a position. Inp re p a ring for this debate, I ended up ove rc o m-ing that hint of doubt by reviewing and re a f-f i rming the main argument in my text. In fulla g reement with Samaja (2000), I refer to the in-dication of plural, multifaceted, and multi-lev-eled nature of health, which can manifest itselfin different hiera rchical planes of complexity.T h u s, Ga d a m e r’s proposition (and Bri c e ñ o -L e ó n’s “intellectual free ri d e”) would only applyto the individual level, where unique, pri va t e,s u b j e c t i ve – in a word, individual – space is re-a l i ze d .

I must also contest Bri c e ñ o - L e ó n’s ve rd i c tthat “Health as a general theory does not ex i s t[because] there are only historical claims”. Tw o

O autor responde The author re p l i e s

Naomar Al m e i d aFi l h o

a s s e rtions result: first, that health is not justi-fied as an object of science; second, that theo-ries are not historical constru c t s. The episte-mological principles that sustain this line of ar-gument are incompatible with the dominanta p p roaches in contempora ry theory of know l-e d g e. It is not the attributes of events or phe-nomena that determine the construction of theobject-model but scientific praxis marked bythe limits and barriers (conditioning factors) ofc o n c rete reality (Samaja, 1994). The theori e s,in turn, are essential tools in the process of con-s t ructing the object, always beginning as “ h i s-t o rical claims” (or knowledge projects) and be-coming both historical and formal constru c t s.

Luiz David Castiel states that the concept ofrisk is “conceptually f r i s k y [undisciplined – T.N . ] ”, in the sense of displaying a certain mutantand imprecise nature. In epistemologicalt e rm s, I do not agre e. T h e re are few objects ofscience with such a ri g o rous degree of form a le l a b o ration as the object-model “ri s k” in thefield of Epidemiology (Miettinen, 1985). As Ihad the opportunity to point out in A Clínica ea Ep i d e m i o l o g i a (Almeida Fi l h o, 1992), thet e rm “ri s k” appears in epidemiological science(and also in Economics) as a theoretical con-cept, in Clinical Medicine as an operational no-tion, and in common social discourse as ap raxeological notion or as “social perc e p t i o n”.Castiel insists and asks: What cut-off pointclearly defines which groups are actually at ri s kand which are not? How does one deal with them o re vulnerable groups (by age, gender, eth-n i c i t y, etc.)? The answer to the first question iss i m p l e, at least in epidemiological terms: thet h reshold for ascribing the risk factor categoryis a re l a t i ve risk of 1.0. For the second question,suffice it to apply the notion of “re f e rence c l a s s-e s” (Bo o r s e, 1977), evaluating normal functionsnot in relation to what is typical (or exc e p t i o n-al) for the species but for what is typical for theclass origin of the subject or group at issue.

Responding directly to other pertinent q u e s-tions by Castiel, I pointed out in the text citeda b ove that the signifier most closely linked tothe popular notion of risk is actually that of“d a n g e r”. Giddens (1990) and Beck (1996), re p-re s e n t a t i ves of an important line of post-Ma rx-ist thought, propose that societies deve l o p e din a certain direction conve rge tow a rds a “s o c i-ety of ri s k”. I thus deem worthy of debateCa s t i e l’s proposition of employing the Sm p Hd e s c riptor for risk also and not only for illness.Yet the only frame of re f e rence for the risk con-cept that I re c o g n i ze as scientifically based isstill Ep i d e m i o l o g y. Respecting the possibilityand validity of approaching risk as a theme in

Page 42: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

ALMEIDA FILHO, N.7 9 4

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

the fields of sociology and anthro p o l o g y, I pre-fer to re s t rict the range of application of con-cepts analyzed herein based on the positionthat precisely there lies its efficacy as a heuri s-tic device.

I thank Castiel for enriching the current de-b a t e, commenting in depth on the topic of pro-t o t y p e s, clarifying its origin and conceptual in-s e rtion. Howe ve r, I disagree on seve ral pointsin this re g a rd. Indeed, Lakoff (1993) does gra n tall the credit to Rosch and his school, but ad-vances considerably in the formal consistencyof the concept and its generalization to otherthemes beyond biology and the psychology ofp e rception. Ro s c h’s theory of prototypes can-not be “amenable to immediate understand-i n g” by fuzzy logic, but Lakoff ’s theory of pro-totypes certainly will be, since the author him-self so indicates based on an analysis of the in-sufficiency of classical logic vis-à-vis the con-ceptual re q u i rements of ambiguous and im-p recise objects. Castiel is right in pointing outthat originally the theory of fuzzy systems didnot mean any break with formal logic butrather an attempt at updating it in terms of cat-e g o ries of gradation. Howe ve r, its subsequentd e velopment outside the technological field(in the narrow sense), principally in the appli-cation to analysis of cultural systems as pro-posed by Lakoff (1993), resulted in an effectivea l t e rn a t i ve to classical logic and the theory ofd i s c rete sets deri ved from it.

In the field of health, there are pra c t i c a l l yno applications of the notion of pro t o t y p e s, de-spite its undeniable proximity to the pro b l e mof superimposed diagnoses or co-morbidity, ashighlighted by Mezzich & Almeida Filho (1994),and to the issue of the fuzzy nature of defini-tion for both exposure and risk in the epidemi-ological frame of re f e rence (Co s t a - Ca p ra ,1995). An interesting recent update on the sub-ject was published by Sa d e g h - Zadeh (2000),emphasizing precisely the theoretical and p ra c-tical uses of fuzzy logic in re s e a rch on health-d i s e a s e.

Castiel, careful as he is (or obsessive, like allus proud children of science), should inve s t i-gate the meaning of “o bve r s e” to determ i n ewhether it is actually fitting to use such a cate-g o ry in the health object. First, I should saythat it is a proposition by Parsons himself(1978), to whom the fair criticism should be ad-d ressed. But since it is no longer fashionable toc ri t i c i ze Parsons for being Parsonian, I contendthat it is a subtle and intelligent indication ofthe dialectic nature of the health-disease dyad.The Brazilian standard dictionary Au r é l i o is notexactly a philosophical source worthy of imme-

diate credit; in addition, the re f e rence to Pa r-sons is clearly metaphorical. Even so, the so-phistic application of the formula “All S is P, byo bversion, will be no S is non-P” by my dearc ritic is correct, and contra ry to what he be-l i e ves to have demonstrated, it contributes tothe notion that health possesses a nature dis-tinct from and irreducible to sickness.

Let us consider, following Ca s t i e l’s line ofa rgument, that P = non(D), or absence of dis-e a s e. Indeed, if (S) = (P), it follows that

(S) = non(D), by obversion, non(S) = non[non(D)] which, by reducing the negation of the n e g a-tion, is equal tonon(S) = (D), thus (S) ≠ (D)It is thus valid to say, on the logical plane,

that it is in fact a relationship of obversion, farf rom re vealing its “f ragility and impro p ri e t y ”.But after all, Castiel is free even to pre s c ri b eb rief and gentle “puzzled pauses [to re g u l a t eour] irre p ressible dri ve to know and pro d u c eo b j e c t s”. But as far as I am concerned, objectsa re precisely the noble product of this peculiarmode of production that constitutes science.

Cecília Minayo observes that “to date, h e a l t hhas never been treated as either a discipline orschool of thought” but rather as a field of k n ow l-edge and pra c t i c e s, in the sense proposed byBo u rdieu (1983). She thus considers it “q u i t ep roblematic to formulate a theory of health orhealth models” even though it may be possible“to theorize the health concept”. In fact, my textwas really not intended to enunciate but to an-nounce a theory, cove ring some essential pre-l i m i n a ry stages for the conceptual constru c-tion pro c e s s. The first stage consisted of a dulyjustified proposition of the positivity of a give nconcept. I do not know if the text succeeded inmeeting this pre re q u i s i t e, but my explicit in-tent was to demonstrate the insufficiency oft h e o retical treatments of the health issue basedon the notion of sickness or disease. The sec-ond stage aimed to refine the concept, makingit more operational as a tool for systematizingthought on a complex object of know l e d g e.With re g a rd to the present effort, I basically at-tempted to present and validate the follow i n gp roposition: similar to the semantic va riety ofthe disease-illness-sickness complex, we s h o u l dc o n s t ruct an equivalent conceptual plura l i t y,identifying va rious modes of health.

Mi n a yo also suggests that I fell into a “t h e o-retical tra p” by identifying only the socio-an-t h ropological and epistemological dimensions

Page 43: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

GENERAL THEORY OF HEALT H 7 9 5

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

as stru c t u ring the health concept, leaving asidethe biological dimension. In addition, she q u e s-tions the ve ry inclusion of the epistemologicaldimension at the same analytical level of thesocial sciences in health. Co n c e rning the omis-sion of the biological dimension, I believe thatMi n a yo is right, but cross-sectional appro a c h-es impose necessary limits on analytical ambi-t i o n s. In this sense, the most I can do is top romise to analyze the biological dimensions u b s e q u e n t l y, in light of the advances and de-bate produced by the text at hand. As to thequestion of whether the epistemological di-mension is stru c t u ring or is part of the meta-analysis of theori e s, I would simply re s p o n dthat this disjunction does not make sense. Ep i s-temology may be stru c t u ring in an early stageof conceptual construction, resuming its meta-t h e o retical or para - t h e o retical mandate assoon as the process of consolidating the objector field adva n c e s.

In the purposive part of her commentary,Mi n a yo contributes with a proposal for differ-entiating health as a total social fact and as aconcept handled by a specific field of pra c t i c e sand policies. She briefly analyzes the notion ofhealth as a good, as a conquest, and as sociale x p ression, with re f e rences to Ma rcel Ma u s s’st h e o ry of the gift, as re t ri e ved by French stru c-t u ralism. She then launches into the confusionof logical types chara c t e rizing W H O ’s elabora-tion on the topic, quoting Ol i ver Sa c k s, whop a ra p h rases Canguilhem, who studies Leri c h e,finally accepting a definition of health-diseasea n c h o red at the individual level. The pro p o s a lof va rious “ h e a l t h s”, my modest contri b u t i o nto the inauguration of this debate, unfort u-nately appears not to have been clear and thusre q u i res ratification. Ac c o rding to my pro p o s i-tion, what Mi n a yo calls health as a total socialfact constitutes just one of the modes of health,p rovisionally designated as “social health” andwhich has its principal descriptor in the sys-tems of signs, meanings, and pra c t i c e s. It is on-ly as a localized indication that I believe healthis theoretically less important as a “social fact”than as a “total fact”.

Dina Cze resnia admits that “no scientificdefinition of health has been found to date,”and that the link between the field of healthand medicine makes it depend on a negativityto define its object. She thus agrees that it isi m p o rtant to attempt to move forw a rd tow a rd sa theory of health destined to support risk pre-vention and health promotion practices (Cz-e resnia, 1999). Ne ve rt h e l e s s, she suggests thatit might be helpful to re t ri e ve the ontologicalconcept of sickness, re c o n s i d e ring “the form in

which this concept is organized in practices thateither favor or jeopardize life”, which could f u n c-tion as a “m a rgin and barri e r” in the process ofconstituting the object of health (practice). Sh ea s k s, “Without the inexo rability of pain andsuffering would a field of health make sense?”And she ends by identifying a possible contra-diction between my tra n s d i s c i p l i n a ry pro p o s-a l / s t a n c e, org a n i zed as a problem or issue andnot as a discipline, and the objective of con-s t ructing a Ge n e ral T h e o ry of He a l t h .

I agree that it would really not be possibleto go too far in the proposed theoretical under-taking without decisively confronting the theo-retical issue of sickness. It is not only the healthconcept that has been neglected. As I analyze din my art i c l e, despite some well-meaning ef-f o rt s, not enough pro g ress has been made ei-ther for a satisfactory composition worthy ofthe name “g e n e ral theory of sickness”. Howe v-e r, I am convinced that it is an articulated pro-ject, but parallel to pro g ress in the reflection onthe concept of health, with distinct objective sand stra t e g i e s. As for the second question, I seeno contradiction between formulating a gener-al (and not unified) theory of health and va l u-ing altern a t i ve and plural modes of under-standing the object. A general theory like theGe n e ral T h e o ry of Systems or the Ge n e ral T h e-o ry of In f o rmation will certainly have a suffi-ciently broad scope to incorporate re s t ri c t e dt h e o ries of health (or middle range theori e s, assuggested by Madel Luz) applied to each re a l m ,plane of emerg e n c e, or facet in the health ob-ject-model.

In the re f e rence to a general theory, asclearly understood by Suely Deslandes in herc o m m e n t a ry, the health object may be in keep-ing with the articulations or interc o n n e c t i o n sb e t ween re s t ricted theories as well as the ef-fects of the hori zontal inva riance in the healthmodels considered. In other word s, “as manyt h e o ries as there [are] altern a t i ve and plura lmodes of approaching this object” mentionedby Cze resnia doubtless need a meta-stru c t u recapable of integrating (and not unifying orm e rely homogenizing) the va rious object-m o d-els comprising the “single plurality” of health.

Taking another angle, Suely De s l a n d e spicks up on the theme of the choice of func-tionalist authors as the target of criticism forthe negative vision of health and demands thatthe analysis include “sociologists incorpora t e dinto the Collective Health debate (like Ha b e r-m a s , Bo u rd i e u , and Gi d d e n s )”. Pe rhaps somei m p o rtant re f e rence has escaped me, but as faras I know none of these authors has dealt di-rectly with the issue of health or sickness. I am

Page 44: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

ALMEIDA FILHO, N.7 9 6

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

u n a w a re of any theory of health in the Fra n k-f u rt school, in French post-stru c t u ralism, or inBritish post-Ma rxism. In the other watershed,as I analyzed in the text at hand, No rth Ameri-can stru c t u ral-functionalism chose the role ofthe sick individual as central to the social sys-tem theory, and interpre t i ve medical anthro-pology proposed a partial theory of disease-ill-n e s s - s i c k n e s s.

Mi n a yo also contends that my text “fails toescape this theoretical entanglement” (anotherway of indicating the purported theore t i c a lt rap) of Anglo-Sa xon reductionist functional-ism, claiming that the re f e rences on which Ibase my analysis forced a superficial and poor-ly systematized discussion of the theory ofhealth. First, all the sociological and anthro p o-logical re f e rences we re used in the article asthe target of criticism and not for theore t i c a ls u p p o rt. Second, the pre l i m i n a ry move m e n tt ow a rds a theory of health could only conc l u d e,and not pre c e d e, a guided process of concep-tual deconstru c t i o n / c o n s t ru c t i o n .

Rita Ba rata also underscores this issue, butre f e r ring to other authors of a Ma rxist re f e r-ence (Si g e rist, Pollack, Ga rcia) who – and here Ido indeed agree – produced theoretical contri-butions on health that could enrich the debate.Even so, and she herself agre e s, none of thema n a l y zed (or even intended to solve) the specif-ic problem of a positive health concept or theabsence-of-disease issue. The contribution byall these authors, defined by their critical s t a n c et ow a rds the functionalist frame of re f e re n c e,could not be useful for the project at hand sim-ply because they do not serve as a target orc o n t rast for the conceptual deconstruction Iattempted to perf o rm .

Ba rata further questions whether the ana-lytical scheme developed by Bibeau & Co ri n ,despite being the only “truly social formulationamong those analyzed by the author, re c ove r i n gthe historical, s o c i a l , and collective dimensionsof the health-disease pro c e s s” is sufficient “t oconsider it an adequate descriptor for the cate-g o ry of social health proposed by the author”.This is apparently a fair and timely cri t i q u e, tothe extent that the choice in fact implies anearly closing of the proposed frame of re f e r-e n c e. Howe ve r, I should point out that all theindications in this conceptual tra j e c t o ry arep rovisional, and this particular one even mores o, given that it does not fit among the basicconcepts of health disciplines, like risk, mor-b i d i t y, measure, etc. As I observe later in thetext, the reshaping of the SmpH theory by oneof its authors in the face of critiques aimed at itin the context of the present debate indicates

that this choice retains its heuristic value vis-à-vis the theme of “social health”.

Madel Luz provides an in-depth discussionof many of the points raised by the text athand. She ascribes the theoretical vacuum inthe health concept to “the predominance of thebiomedical frame of re f e rence in the social sci-e n c e s”, in culture, and in basic societal re l a-t i o n s. I confess that it remained beyond thescope of my analysis to investigate the deter-minants of this conceptual blind spot in thesocial history of We s t e rn science, as Luz her-self did (1989) in a pertinent and competentw a y. Re f e r ring to Foucault, she points to theinstitutional order of the biomedical and so-cial disciplinary fields as a “set of identifica-tions which ‘ex p e l s’ f rom its theoretical nucleussuch positivities as health, l i f e , or vitality”. How-e ve r, she re c o g n i zes that a positive conceptu-alization of health invo l ves the epistemologi-cal and institutional deconstruction of the“medical ord e r”.

I am happy with the degree of understand-ing of my text’s objectives as displayed by Lu z ,a partner in lengthy debates on the Co l l e c t i veHealth object-model. As I said above, I ammodestly happy with the claim to an epistemo-logical deconstruction of an incipient concep-tual order (the field of Co l l e c t i ve Health), but Iwould not dare to expand the scope of the pro-posed critical interf e rence to include an insti-tutional order subject to such deeply estab-lished determ i n a t i o n s. I agree both with herw a rnings concerning the danger of unified the-o ries which historically take biomedicine asthe basis for unification (note that my pro p o s a lis precisely the contra ry) as well as with herrecommendation to seek a general theory as afinishing line and not as a point of depart u re.

Ju randir Fre i re Costa raises the question ofc o g n i t i ve models and the necessary levels ofa b s t raction to foster reflection on a GTH whenhe recommends “renouncing the intention toconstruct a meta-theory of health in favor ofp rompt descriptions, subject to revision and fur-ther in-depth deve l o p m e n t”. As a collabora t i o nto simplify re s e a rch pro t o c o l s, he proposes todivide the health field into two sets: that ofphysicalist descriptions – facts postulated ascausally independent of meaning and that ofmentalist descriptions – all of the mentallyphenomenic “q u a l i t a t i ve” aspects of the healthe x p e ri e n c e. He ends by suggesting pra c t i c a lmodes of implementing this strategy for thet h e o retical construction of the health object,re f e r ring to the difficulties in ensuring compat-ibility among disciplines and the levels of so-cial validation needed for such a pro p o s a l .

Page 45: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

GENERAL THEORY OF HEALT H 7 9 7

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

Such suggestions provide valuable contri-butions to the project, but I would like to dis-cuss some specific points. First, to consolidatea meta-theory or general theory is not incom-patible with developing re s t ricted theori e sbased on specific deve l o p m e n t s. As I have al-ready discussed in responding to De s l a n d e sand Mi n a yo, and in total agreement with Luz, Ib e l i e ve it is desirable to conduct a parallel de-velopment of the general theory and the re-s t ricted theories of health-disease in order tomutually feed the processes of systematizingthe cognitive models (or object-models, inBungean terminology).

Second, as for the phenomenic sets pro-posed by Fre i re Costa, I believe that it is anoth-er issue of the level or plane of emerg e n c e, inwhich one should also consider mixed descri p-tions (physicalist and mentalist, parallel orc o n ve rgent – hence the risk concept is cert a i n-ly the best example). Fi n a l l y, I agree with thelimited feasibility of obliging “s p e c i a l i s t s” tocommand distinct areas of know l e d g e, give nthat encyclopedism as a project has long sincevanished. Howe ve r, as I indicated in anothers e ries of articles (Almeida Fi l h o, 1997, 1998,2000), a pragmatic proposal for tra n s d i s c i p l i-n a rity can deal with the necessary synthesis ofhealth as an object-model, single and plural, bymeans of a new encyclopedism based on thec i rculation of subjects and not the transfer ofd i s c i p l i n a ry discourses. In my opinion the con-clusion to the commentary by Fre i re Costa isp e rfect: we must respect the language of thep a radigms without confusing incommensura-bility with untra n s l a t a b i l i t y.

Jaime Breilh considers the discussion of aGe n e ral T h e o ry of Health timely, precisely atthis moment in which what are called “g e n e ra lscientific fra m e w o rk s” are being questioned. Ithank him for his series of positive commentson my proposition and move on immediatelyto deal with the critical points he identified.First, Breilh cri t i c i zes the exc e s s i ve dependen-cy on the text’s line of argument in relation toEu ropean thought and its successors. He isright on this point. Of course the import a n tc o n t ribution by the Argentine philosopherJuan Samaja alone could not counterbalancethe conceptual construction on the theme ofsickness perf o rmed by the social sciences ap-plied to health in the Anglo-Sa xon context orthe French epistemological tradition. The workof Breilh himself (1990, 1995), and that of Pe-d ro Luiz Castellanos (1997), Luiz David Ca s t i e l(1994), José Ricardo Ay res (1997), Dina Cze re s-nia (1999), and many others have cert a i n l yc o n t ributed greatly to the robustness of the ar-

gument. What I can say is that I consider thema “t h e o retical re s e rve” for subsequent stages inthe conceptual construction process thatawaits us.

Second, Breilh introduces a subtle cri t i q u et ow a rds the academicism and elitism of my ar-g u m e n t s, highlighting that the construction ofa scientific discourse on health is too serious amatter to be left exc l u s i vely to scientists. Hecontends that a Ge n e ral T h e o ry of He a l t h“should encompass the historical subjects mo-b i l i zed around the object as a field of action”,but he does not identify such a possibility inmy proposition. He recommends that the nec-e s s a ry theoretical construction be conductedbased on the dissolution of separations be-t ween “s u b j e c t”, “o b j e c t i ve world”, and “m a s s”imposed by positivist rationalism. In short, hep roposes to radically politicize any attempt atd e veloping theories of health, whether genera lor re s t ricted, employing a re f e rence from mul-t i c u l t u ralism that shifts from the original an-t h ropological extraction to a vo l u n t a rist mili-tant version.

In this re g a rd, Breilh and I harbor a ra d i c a ld i s a g reement: while he believes that the per-sons who are the object of re s e a rch are subjectsfully capable of directly grasping the process ofp roducing knowledge on their own live s, con-t e x t s, and systems of thought, I contend thatre s e a rch is a professional practice exercised bythose who undergo stru c t u red processes oft h e o retical and methodological training. T h ec o n c rete subjects constitute subjects of theirown lives and health, I agre e, but the agentswho produce re s e a rch are subjects of a pecu-liar institutional and ideological order which,whether we like it or not, achieves re l a t i ve so-cial and political autonomy in We s t e rn socialf o rm a t i o n s. As acknowledged by Bibeau (seeb e l ow), the notion of social health and the re f-e rence to SmpH implies a conscious and feasi-ble opening tow a rds social discourses on h e a l t hand its corre l a t e s, mediated by re s e a rch pra x i s.

Gilles Bibeau, one of the authors of the the-o ry of “systems of signs, m e a n i n g s , and pra c-tices in health”, re c o g n i zes that few anthro p o l-ogists have taken interest in developing an an-t h ropology of health as opposed to the per-s p e c t i ve of disease pre vailing in this field. Bypositioning himself vis-à-vis the nature of pop-ular semeiologies as the basis of belief systemsand the role of science as a social and histori-cal response to human demands (including de-mands for health), he takes a stance that sur-mounts the romantic ethnoscience move m e n tin vogue in the 1960s. He uses these founda-tions to “enthusiastically” support both the

Page 46: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

ALMEIDA FILHO, N.7 9 8

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

Ge n e ral T h e o ry of Health project and the de-c o n s t ructionist and integralizing strategy pur-sued in the text at hand. He presents a ro b u s tline of argument supporting what he considersc o n ve rgence in our reflection: the search forpositivity in the concept, anchored in the dis-course of science, in parallel with the intro d u c-tion of what he calls “local epistemologies” inthe construction of a Ge n e ral T h e o ry of He a l t h .

Bibeau effectively “ b u y s” the ideas of con-ceptual plurality and tra n s d i s c i p l i n a ri t y, align-ing strategic themes to support the pro p o s a lunder debate. He begins by discussing the“quest for perfect health” and the “we l l - b e i n gc o m p l e x” as stru c t u ring symbolic sets in thedominant ideology in post-industrial capitalistc o u n t ri e s, in which notions like promotion andp re vention provide the basis for technologicalu n d e rtakings in social intervention. Next, hea p p roaches the contempora ry trend to consid-er the historicity and relativity of biology, sug-gesting that perspectives be opened for a newand solid integration between socio-cultura land biodynamic health para d i g m s. He enri c h-es the line of argument proposed in my text byi n t roducing the linguistic issue as the basis forsymbolic and phenomenological analysis ofthe health-disease complex and its effects andc o r re l a t i o n s. He then re a f f i rms the position ofc o n s i d e ring interconnections between collec-t i ve systems of meaning, local health idioms,and individual discourses of well-being as es-sential to articulate a theoretical model ofhealth which in fact respects the complexity ofthe corresponding phenomenic pro c e s s e s.Evaluating this section of his commentary, Inote with great satisfaction that Bibeau intendsto move forw a rd with the theory of “systems ofs i g n s, meanings, and practices in health”, ab-sorbing and incorporating the critique that thist h e o ry remained committed to illness models.

In the second part of his commentary,Bibeau aims to contribute to the strategic partof the process of theoretical construction, em-phasizing the value of “local epistemologies”for integralizing the health object. He initiallyjustifies this perspective based on the notion ofc u l t u ral complexity (Ha n n e rz, 1993), pointingout its dialectic nature as a concept based onc o n t ra d i c t o ry pairs like local-global, center- p e-ri p h e ry, inclusion-exclusion, and majori t y- m i-n o ri t y. As both a challenge and a pro m i s i n gway out, he comprehends the processes of“c re o l i z a t i o n” of societies and their cultura ls y s t e m s. He then takes advantage of the oppor-tunity of this debate to indicate that, given thatscience also constitutes an ideological and in-stitutional network that is part of the modernWe s t’s cultural system, it is licit to consider thepossibility of a “c re o l i zed science”.

In the case of the health sciences and theirh y b rid, plural, and imprecise objects, Bi b e a uu n veils the important role of local epistemolo-g i e s, which found “popular diseases” and “s e-mantic health network s” on the basis of “ i m-plicit health theori e s”. The exploration of suchelements by means of competent ethnogra p h i ca p p ro a c h e s, conscious of their limits as “ l o c a lk n ow l e d g e” (Ge e rtz, 2000), constitutes a re q u i-site for grasping the “systems of signs, mean-i n g s, and practices in health” which, withg reater pro p riety after this, is justified as a de-s c riptor of “social health” or “health imagi-n a ry ”. In this sense, Bibeau concludes with aquote by No rth American re s e a rcher Vi c t o rTu rn e r, who launched an important line of an-t h ropological investigation of suffering, high-lighting an expression which in my view willconstitute a basic notion for future ethno-g rafies of “social health”, becoming a key con-cept for any creole grammar of the health-dis-ease complex: “the good life”. But this is thesubject for a new debate. . .

Page 47: 2001-Filho-1 REF03.pdf

GENERAL THEORY OF HEALT H 7 9 9

Cad. Saúde Pública, Rio de Janeiro, 17(4):753-799, jul-ago, 2001

R e f e re n c e s

ALMEIDA FILHO, N., 1992. A Clínica e a Ep i d e m i o l o-g i a. Sa l va d o r: APCE/Rio de Ja n e i ro: ABRASCO.

ALMEIDA FILHO, N., 1997. Tra n s d i s c i p l i n a ridade esaúde coletiva. Ciência & Saúde Coletiva , 2 : 5 - 2 0 .

ALMEIDA FILHO, N., 1998. So b re as relações entrecomplexidade e tra n s d i s c i p l i n a ridade em saúde.Revista da ABEM, 2 2 : 2 2 - 3 0 .

ALMEIDA FILHO, N., 2000. In t e r s e t o rialidade e tra n s-d i s c i p l i n a ridade em saúde. Revista Bra s i l e i ra deAd m i n i s t ração Pública, 3 4 : 1 1 - 3 4 .

AYRES, J. R., 1997. S o b re o Risco – Pa ra Compre e n d e ra Ep i d e m i o l o g i a. São Paulo: Ed i t o ra Hu c i t e c.

BECK, U., 1996. La sociedad del ri e s g o. In: Las Conce-cuencias Pe rversas de la Mo d e r n i d a d : Mo d e r n i-d a d , Contingencia y Riesgo (J. Be riain, org.), pp.182-201, Ba rcelona: Anthro p o s.

BOORSE, C., 1977. Health as a theoretical concept.Philosophy of Science, 44:542-573.

BOURDIEU, P., 1983. O campo científico. In: P i e r reBo u rd i e u :S o c i o l o g i a (R. Ortiz, org.), pp. 122-155,São Paulo: Ed i t o ra Ática.

BREILH, J., 1995. Ep i d e m i o l o g y ’s role in the cre a t i o nof a humane world: Co n ve rgences and dive r-gences among the schools. Social Science andMe d i c i n e , 4 1 : 9 1 1 - 9 1 4 .

BREILH, J., 1990. Re p rodução social e inve s t i g a ç ã oem saúde coletiva. Co n s t rução do pensamento ed e b a t e. In: Ep i d e m i o l o g i a , Teoria e Ob j e t o ( D. C.Costa, org.), pp. 137-165, São Paulo: Ed i t o ra Hu c i-t e c / A B R A S CO.

C A S T E L LANOS, P., 1997. Epidemiologia, salud publi-ca, situación de salud y condiciones de vida. In :Condiçoes de Vida e Situação de Saúde (R. Ba ra t a ,o rg.), pp. 24-32, Rio de Ja n e i ro: Ed i t o ra Fi o c ru z /A B R A S CO.

CASTIEL, L. D., 1994. O Bu raco e o Avestruz – A Si n g u-laridade do Adoecer Hu m a n o. Campinas: Pa p i ru s.

CO S TA-CAPRA, R., 1995. Fuzzy logic and epidemio-logic reasoning. In: II Co n g resso Ib e ro - A m e ri-cano de Epidemiologia, III Co n g resso Bra s i l e i rode Epidemiologia, Re s u m o s, p. 305. Sa l va d o r:A B R A S CO.

CZERESNIA, D., 1999. The concept of health and thed i f f e rence between pre vention and pro m o t i o n .Cadernos de Saúde Pública, 1 5 : 7 0 1 - 7 0 9 .

GADAMER, H.-G., 1996. The Enigma of He a l t h. Be rk e-l e y: St a n f o rd Un i versity Pre s s.

G E E RTZ, C., 2000. “Local know l e d g e” and its limits.In: Available Li g h t : An t h ropological Reflections onPhilosophical To p i c s (C. Ge e rtz, ed.), pp. 133-142,Princeton: Princeton Un i versity Pre s s.

GIDDENS, A., 1990. The Consequences of Mo d e r n i t y.Ca m b ridge: Polity Pre s s.

HANNERZ, U., 1993. Cu l t u ral Complex i t y : Studies inthe Social Organization of Me a n i n g . New Yo rk :Columbia Un i versity Pre s s.

LA KO F F, G., 1993. Wo m e n , Fi re and Da n g e ro u sT h i n g s. Be rk e l e y: Un i versity of Ca l i f o rnia Pre s s.

LUZ, M., 1989. Na t u ra l ,R a c i o n a l ,S o c i a l. Rio de Ja n e i-ro: Gra a l .

MEZZICH, J. & ALMEIDA FILHO, N., 1994. Ep i d e m i-ology and diagnostic systems in psyc h i a t ry. Ac t aPsychiatrica Scandinavica, 9 0 ( Su p. 385):61-65.

M I E TTINEN, O., 1985. T h e o retical Ep i d e m i o l o gy. Ne wYo rk: John Wiley & So n s.

PARSONS, T., 1978. Action Theory and Human Condi-t i o n. New Yo rk: Free Pre s s.

S A D E G H - ZADEH, K., 2000. Fuzzy health, illness, andd i s e a s e. Journal of Medicine & Ph i l o s o p h y, 25:6 0 5 - 6 3 8 .

SAMAJA, J., 1994. Epistemologia y Me t o d o l o g í a. Bu e-nos Aires: EUDEBA.

SAMAJA, J., 2000. A Re p rodução Social e a Saúde. Sa l-va d o r: Casa da Sa ú d e.